What an Average Semantics Needs

The mystery of (1a-b) is that it seems that they can be true, even though there is no person in the world that is the reference of the noun phrases the average American and the average Freddie Voter, and no person in the world that has 2.3 children. (1c) makes a similar point, though in a somewhat different fashion: while the property of seeing one’s doctor 7.5 times per year is not incoherent in the same way as the property of having 2.3 children, the truth of (1c) does not commit us to the existence of any individuals who actually have this property. Both linguists and philosophers have used average sentences to draw dramatic conclusions of various sorts. For example, Norbert Hornstein and Noam Chomsky have used this class of sentences to argue that semantic theory does not exploit a reference relation, a relation between words and things (Hornstein 1984, Chomsky 2000). Similarly, some philosophers have used these sentences to argue that singular reference is not ontologically committing. Such conclusions are far too hasty. Those who based dramatic conclusions about the nature of semantics or ontological commitment on average sentences are unfairly exploiting the lack of a compositional semantics for sentences of this sort. In this paper, we provide the first such semantics. Moreover, we show that within the referential approach to semantics one can provide a detailed compositional semantics of these constructions that reveals much of specific linguistic interest. Specifically, average sentences provide new evidence that the compositional system of natural language must allow for the possibility that the nuclear scope of of a scope-taking term may serve as the argument of a third expression, rather than the scope-taking term itself, a relation that Barker (2007) refers to as PARASITIC SCOPE.

[1]  Aram A. Yengoyan,et al.  Modes of Comparison , 2006 .

[2]  Christopher Kennedy,et al.  On 'average' , 2009 .

[3]  Godehard Link The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice‐theoretical Approach , 2008 .

[4]  Francis Jeffry Pelletier,et al.  The Average American has 2.3 Children , 2002, J. Semant..

[5]  Pauline Jacobson Towards a Variable-Free Semantics , 1999 .

[6]  Bernhard Thalheim,et al.  About Semantics , 2010, SDKB.

[7]  Edward L. Keenan,et al.  A semantic characterization of natural language determiners , 1986 .

[8]  Norbert Hornstein,et al.  Logic as Grammar , 1984 .

[9]  J. Barwise,et al.  Generalized quantifiers and natural language , 1981 .

[10]  Uriel Weinreich,et al.  On semantics , 1980 .

[11]  B. Carpenter,et al.  Type-Logical Semantics , 1997 .

[12]  Jacob Hoeksema,et al.  Negative polarity and the comparative , 1983 .

[13]  Joan Bresnan,et al.  Syntax of the Comparative Clause Construction in English , 1973 .

[14]  Christopher Kennedy,et al.  Comparative Deletion And Optimality In Syntax , 2002 .

[15]  R. Bhatt,et al.  Direct Comparisons: Resurrecting the Direct Analysis of Phrasal Comparatives , 2007 .

[16]  K Manfred,et al.  FOUR THOUSAND SHIPS PASSED THROUGH THE LOCK: OBJECT-INDUCED MEASURE FUNCTIONS ON EVENTS , 1990 .

[17]  M. Cresswell THE SEMANTICS OF DEGREE , 1976 .

[18]  Irene Heim,et al.  Semantics in generative grammar , 1998 .

[19]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  On Wh-Movement , 1977 .

[20]  Manfred Krifka,et al.  Nominal Reference, Temporal Constitution and Quantification in Event Semantics , 1989 .

[21]  Irene Heim,et al.  The Semantics of Degree , 2002 .

[22]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind: References , 2000 .

[23]  C. Heycock Asymmetries in reconstruction , 1995 .

[24]  Martin Hackl,et al.  Comparative Quantifiers and Plural Predication , 2001 .

[25]  Petra Hendriks,et al.  Review of C. Kennedy, Projecting the adjective. The syntax and semantics of gradability and comparison , 1999 .