Generalization in Decision Research: The Role of Formal Models

A generalization is a working hypothesis, typically expressed in the form of cause-effect relations. Generalizations decay because a) it is difficult to identify appropriate cause-effect relations and b) such relations are sensitive to the influences of environmental conditions. Whereas scientists should be realistic in their aspirations to create generalizable knowledge, much can be done to improve performance through more extensive use of formal models. Two basic types of model are distinguished: replica models and symbolic models. It is particularly important that theories permit comparisons between models and data at multiple levels involving processes, environmental conditions, and predictions. Scientists should avoid the extremes of " models without data" and "data without models." Symbolic models should be subjected to "strong" empirical tests via predictions (rather than tests of statistical significance), and the competing predictions of alternatives. In addition to suggesting what experimental evidence should be collected, it is proposed that symbolic models also serve the important function of determining when data collection would be of little value. The nature of evidence generated by replica models (i. e., experiments) is considered from three viewpoints: 1) asymmetries in the way data and theory interact in affecting conclusions; 2) apparent but illusory conflicts between the goals of internal and external validity; and 3) the importance of conducting experiments despite poor prospects of creating knowledge that can be generalized.

[1]  Howard Kunreuther,et al.  Ambiguity and Insurance Decisions , 1985 .

[2]  Karl E. Weick,et al.  An Assessment Of Laboratory Experiments In Accounting , 1982 .

[3]  Magoroh Maruyama,et al.  THE SECOND CYBERNETICS Deviation-Amplifying Mutual Causal Processes , 1963 .

[4]  Daniel Kahneman,et al.  Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability , 1973 .

[5]  E. Boring,et al.  The nature and history of experimental control. , 1954, The American journal of psychology.

[6]  Alphonse Chapanis,et al.  Men, machines, and models. , 1961 .

[7]  L. Cronbach Beyond the Two Disciplines of Scientific Psychology. , 1975 .

[8]  Ronald C. Serlin,et al.  Rationality in psychological research: The good-enough principle. , 1985 .

[9]  R. Hogarth,et al.  Judging probable cause. , 1986 .

[10]  R. Hogarth,et al.  Confidence in judgment: Persistence of the illusion of validity. , 1978 .

[11]  Charles R. Plott,et al.  Industrial Organization Theory and Experimental Economies , 1982 .

[12]  A. Bandura The self system in reciprocal determinism. , 1978 .

[13]  M. Lombardo,et al.  Mutual Restraint in Tree Swallows: A Test of the TIT FOR TAT Model of Reciprocity , 1985, Science.

[14]  A Chapanis,et al.  The relevance of laboratory studies to practical situations. , 1967, Ergonomics.

[15]  M. Allais Le comportement de l'homme rationnel devant le risque : critique des postulats et axiomes de l'ecole americaine , 1953 .

[16]  V. Smith Microeconomic Systems as an Experimental Science , 1982 .

[17]  W. Hofstee,et al.  METHODOLOGICAL DECISION RULES AS RESEARCH POLICIES - A BETTING RECONSTRUCTION OF EMPIRICAL-RESEARCH , 1984 .

[18]  H. Kunreuther Disaster Insurance Protection: Public Policy Lessons , 1978 .

[19]  Murray S. Davis,et al.  That's Interesting! , 1971 .

[20]  R. Hogarth Beyond discrete biases: Functional and dysfunctional aspects of judgmental heuristics. , 1981 .

[21]  P. Meehl Theoretical risks and tabular asterisks: Sir Karl, Sir Ronald, and the slow progress of soft psychology. , 1978 .

[22]  W. Hamilton,et al.  The evolution of cooperation. , 1984, Science.

[23]  H. J. Einhorn,et al.  Linear regression and process-tracing models of judgment. , 1979 .

[24]  R M Hogarth Monozygotic and dizygotic twins reared together: sensitivity of heritability estimates. , 1974, The British journal of mathematical and statistical psychology.

[25]  D. Krantz,et al.  The use of statistical heuristics in everyday inductive reasoning , 1983 .

[26]  H. Simon Rational Decision Making in Business Organizations , 1978 .

[27]  Kenneth R. Hammond Generalization in Operational Contexts: What Does It Mean? Can It be Done? , 1986, IEEE Transactions on Systems, Man, and Cybernetics.

[28]  E. Fama EFFICIENT CAPITAL MARKETS: A REVIEW OF THEORY AND EMPIRICAL WORK* , 1970 .

[29]  R. Hogarth,et al.  BEHAVIORAL DECISION THEORY: PROCESSES OF JUDGMENT AND CHOICE , 1981 .

[30]  J. Mackie,et al.  The cement of the universe : a study of causation , 1977 .

[31]  R. Thaler Toward a positive theory of consumer choice , 1980 .

[32]  D. Campbell III. “Degrees of Freedom” and the Case Study , 1975 .

[33]  E. Brunswik,et al.  The Conceptual Framework of Psychology , 1954 .

[34]  R. Hogarth,et al.  Prediction, Diagnosis, and Causal Thinking in Forecasting , 1982 .

[35]  Robin M. Hogarth,et al.  Discussion of An Assessment of Laboratory Experiments in Accounting , 1982 .

[36]  A. Tversky,et al.  Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases , 1974, Science.

[37]  J. Kagel,et al.  Income-Leisure Tradeoffs of Animal Workers , 1981 .

[38]  C. Coombs,et al.  Single-Peaked Functions and the Theory of Preference , 1977 .

[39]  J. Platt Strong Inference: Certain systematic methods of scientific thinking may produce much more rapid progress than others. , 1964, Science.

[40]  D. Campbell Blind variation and selective retention in creative thought as in other knowledge processes. , 1960, Psychological review.

[41]  J. Armstrong Advocacy and Objectivity in Science , 1979 .

[42]  John W. Payne,et al.  Contingent decision behavior. , 1982 .

[43]  A. Tversky,et al.  Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment , 1983 .