Risk and Prisoner's Dilemma: A Reinterpretation of Coombs' Re‐parameterization

We propose a model to measure risk in a prisoner’s dilemma based on Coombs’ (1973) re‐parameterization of the game as an individual risk decision‐making task that chooses between a gamble of cooperation and another gamble of defection. Specifically, we propose an index, r ,t o represent the risk associated with cooperation relative to defection. In conjunction with Rapoport’s (1967) index of cooperation (K), our formulation of risk allows us to construct games that vary in risk (as indexed by r) while controlling for cooperativeness (as indexed by K). Following utility analysis that models risk seeking as a convex utility function and risk averse as a concave function, we predict that risk‐ seeking people cooperate more in games that the cooperation choice is more risky, whereas risk‐averse people cooperate more in games that the cooperation choice is less risky. In the three studies that we varied game parameters, used different measures of risk orientation and prosocial orientation and used different experimental procedures, we found robust results supporting our predictions. Theoretical analysis of our formulation further suggests that risk and cooperativeness of a prisoner’s dilemma game is not entirely independent. Games that have a higher cooperativeness index are necessarily more risky. Copyright © 2011 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. A prisoner’s dilemma (PD) models a mixed‐motive situation that individual rationality leads to a collective suboptimal outcome. Table1 presents aPDgame following Rapoport and Chammah’s (1965) payoff notations. When both players choose the C‐choice, both receive the reward outcome (R). When both players choose the D‐choice, both receive the punishment outcome (P). When one chooses C and the other chooses D, the C‐choice player receives the sucker outcome (S), whereas the D‐choice player receives the temptation outcome(T).APDgamehasauniquestructureofT>R>P>S

[1]  N. Chater,et al.  Game relativity: how context influences strategic decision making. , 2006, Journal of experimental psychology. Learning, memory, and cognition.

[2]  Scott B. MacKenzie,et al.  Common method biases in behavioral research: a critical review of the literature and recommended remedies. , 2003, The Journal of applied psychology.

[3]  D. M. Kuhlman,et al.  Individual differences in game motivation as moderators of preprogrammed strategy effects in prisoner's dilemma. , 1975, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[4]  P. V. Lange,et al.  The pursuit of joint outcomes and equality in outcomes: An integrative model of social value orientation. , 1999 .

[5]  Elke U. Weber,et al.  A descriptive measure of risk , 1988 .

[6]  John C. Butler,et al.  Measures of Perceived Risk , 1999 .

[7]  E. Weber,et al.  A Domain-Specific Risk-Attitude Scale: Measuring Risk Perceptions and Risk Behaviors , 2002 .

[8]  Clyde H. Coombs,et al.  A reparameterization of the prisoner's dilemma game , 1973 .

[9]  Jeffrey D. Berejikian Revolutionary Collective Action and the Agent-Structure Problem , 1992, American Political Science Review.

[10]  Wim B. G. Liebrand,et al.  The ring measure of social values: A computerized procedure for assessing individual differences in information processing and social value orientation , 1988 .

[11]  Werner Raub,et al.  Gains, losses, and cooperation in social dilemmas and collective action: The effects of risk preferences , 1997 .

[12]  Anatol Rapoport,et al.  A note on the "index of cooperation" for Prisoner's Dilemma , 1967 .

[13]  Asim Karim,et al.  Automatic Personalized Spam Filtering through Significant Word Modeling , 2007 .

[14]  N. Kerr Motivation losses in small groups: a social dilemma analysis , 1983 .

[15]  W. Raub,et al.  REVOLUTION AND RISK , 1998 .

[16]  J. Tedeschi,et al.  Matrix indices and strategy choices in mixed-motive games , 1967 .

[17]  S. Komorita,et al.  A model of the N-person dilemma-type game , 1976 .