Investigating the Neural and Cognitive Basis of Moral Luck: It’s Not What You Do but What You Know

Moral judgments, we expect, ought not to depend on luck. A person should be blamed only for actions and outcomes that were under the person’s control. Yet often, moral judgments appear to be influenced by luck. A father who leaves his child by the bath, after telling his child to stay put and believing that he will stay put, is judged to be morally blameworthy if the child drowns (an unlucky outcome), but not if his child stays put and doesn’t drown. Previous theories of moral luck suggest that this asymmetry reflects primarily the influence of unlucky outcomes on moral judgments. In the current study, we use behavioral methods and fMRI to test an alternative: these moral judgments largely reflect participants’ judgments of the agent’s beliefs. In “moral luck” scenarios, the unlucky agent also holds a false belief. Here, we show that moral luck depends more on false beliefs than bad outcomes. We also show that participants with false beliefs are judged as having less justified beliefs and are therefore judged as more morally blameworthy. The current study lends support to a rationalist account of moral luck: moral luck asymmetries are driven not by outcome bias primarily, but by mental state assessments we endorse as morally relevant, i.e. whether agents are justified in thinking that they won’t cause harm.

[1]  N. Richards Luck and Desert , 1986 .

[2]  K. Zilles,et al.  Mind Reading: Neural Mechanisms of Theory of Mind and Self-Perspective , 2001, NeuroImage.

[3]  J. Stanley Knowledge and Practical Interests , 2005 .

[4]  R. Saxe,et al.  Innocent intentions: A correlation between forgiveness for accidental harm and neural activity , 2009, Neuropsychologia.

[5]  Richard S. J. Frackowiak,et al.  Other minds in the brain: a functional imaging study of “theory of mind” in story comprehension , 1995, Cognition.

[6]  Bertram F. Malle,et al.  Can Unintended Side Effects Be Intentional? Resolving a Controversy Over Intentionality and Morality , 2010, Personality & social psychology bulletin.

[7]  Rebecca Saxe,et al.  The influence of prior record on moral judgment , 2008, Neuropsychologia.

[8]  Aaron C. Koralek,et al.  Two Takes on the Social Brain: A Comparison of Theory of Mind Tasks , 2007, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience.

[9]  H. Walter,et al.  The intentional network: How the brain reads varieties of intentions , 2007, Neuropsychologia.

[10]  T. Nagel Moral Luck , 2009 .

[11]  R Saxe,et al.  People thinking about thinking people The role of the temporo-parietal junction in “theory of mind” , 2003, NeuroImage.

[12]  J. Haidt The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. , 2001, Psychological review.

[13]  F. Cushman Crime and punishment: Distinguishing the roles of causal and intentional analyses in moral judgment , 2008, Cognition.

[14]  Joshua Knobe,et al.  Theory of mind and moral cognition: exploring the connections , 2005, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[15]  Andrew D. Engell,et al.  The Neural Bases of Cognitive Conflict and Control in Moral Judgment , 2004, Neuron.

[16]  Rebecca Saxe,et al.  An fMRI Investigation of Spontaneous Mental State Inference for Moral Judgment , 2009, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience.

[17]  Wesley Buckwalter,et al.  The Epistemic Side-Effect Effect , 2010 .

[18]  R. Poldrack Can cognitive processes be inferred from neuroimaging data? , 2006, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[19]  M. Alicke Culpable control and the psychology of blame. , 2000, Psychological bulletin.

[20]  J. Decety,et al.  What you believe versus what you think they believe: a neuroimaging study of conceptual perspective‐taking , 2003, The European journal of neuroscience.

[21]  Edward B. Royzman,et al.  Is Consequential Luck Morally Inconsequential? Empirical Psychology and the Reassessment of Moral Luck , 2004 .

[22]  B. Rosebury Moral Responsibility and “Moral Luck” , 1995 .

[23]  Joshua Knobe,et al.  The Pervasive Impact of Moral Judgment , 2009 .

[24]  J. Hull,et al.  Practical Interests, Relevant Alternatives, and Knowledge Attributions: an Empirical Study , 2008, Review of philosophy and psychology.

[25]  Bernard Williams,et al.  Moral Luck: Moral luck , 1981 .

[26]  R. Saxe,et al.  The neural basis of the interaction between theory of mind and moral judgment , 2007, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.

[27]  Keith DeRose Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions , 1992 .

[28]  Yarrow Dunham,et al.  Judgments of the Lucky across Development and Culture , 2022 .

[29]  J. Baron,et al.  Outcome bias in decision evaluation. , 1988, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[30]  Jonathan D. Cohen,et al.  An fMRI Investigation of Emotional Engagement in Moral Judgment , 2001, Science.

[31]  S. Guttenplan Mind and language , 1975 .

[32]  C. Frith,et al.  Reading the mind in cartoons and stories: an fMRI study of ‘theory of mind’ in verbal and nonverbal tasks , 2000, Neuropsychologia.

[33]  W. Tyndale,et al.  Development and Culture , 2002 .

[34]  Rebecca Saxe,et al.  The neural basis of belief encoding and integration in moral judgment , 2008, NeuroImage.

[35]  Elizabeth S Spelke,et al.  Children's Biased Evaluations of Lucky Versus Unlucky People and Their Social Groups , 2006, Psychological science.

[36]  Uta Frith,et al.  Theory of mind , 2001, Current Biology.