Linguistics and the Scientific Method

ABSTRACT. In the present paper, I contrast empirical and non-empirical approaches to linguistics by examining the extent to which they practice the scientific method. I provide examples of linguistic analyses that follow and depart from the scientific method and argue that valid explanations about actual language processing rely on adherence to scientific methodology. However, this is not a requirement for philosophical arguments about abstract language structure. Charges of pseudoscience arise when empirical significance is attached to analyses that fail to follow the scientific method. Progress in linguistics is only made to the extent that researchers adopt the method that is standard in scientific endeavors. 1. INTRODUCTION. If you were to randomly select an introductory science textbook the chances are very high that you would find a section dedicated to the scientific method. The steps of the scientific method are usually enumerated in this way: (1) Observe a phenomenon. (2) Formulate a hypothesis to explain it. (3) Carry out an experiment or collect other observations to test the hypothesis. (4) Analyze the results to determine whether they confirm or refute the hypothesis. Studies which follow these steps are considered empirical or scientific. Of course, not every field of study is scientific. Literature, philosophy, pure mathematics, formal logic, and art are examples of these. All of them are worthy areas of inquiry even though they are not scientific, and in general they do not purport to be. In contrast, some fields have all the trappings of a scientific enterprise, but unlike philosophy or literature, for instance, they appear to make scientific assertions. Such enterprises are considered pseudosciences because they make scientific sounding claims but arrive at their conclusions without follow the scientific method. Astrology, extra-sensory perception, UFOlogy, and studies that tout magic diet pills fall into this category. Besides their failure to follow scientific method, pseudosciences demonstrate a number of other characteristics as well (Ruscio 2002): (1) (1) They ignore contradictory evidence. (2) Their proponents often react in a hostile manner when their orthodoxy ms challenged. (3) They use an inordinate amount of technical jargon. (4) The correctness of their ideas is supported by argumentation, reasoning, intuition, introspection, and reference to authority figures rather than tangible evidence. (5) Very little new real-world knowledge is produced. (6) It is impossible to subject their theories to scrutiny. (6) Explanations are vague and often involve scientific terms used out of context. My contention in this paper is not to argue that the whole of linguistics is either scientific or pseudoscientific. It is patently unfair to subsume entire fields under one rubric or another since there is a great deal of diversity regarding how individual studies are carried out. I will, in fact, review some instances of pseudoscientific physics. However, the principal focus of this paper is to evaluate specific linguistic analyses and hypotheses in terms of their adherence to the scientific method. It is my hope that a discussion of scientific methodology will highlight the importance of well-designed experimental and quantitative analyses, and how these lead to progress in understanding linguistic processes. 2. OBSERVATION. The first step in the scientific method is to observe some phenomenon. Linguists are masters of observation and hardly an observable generalization is left untouched in some framework. Slips-of-the-tongue, bizarre syntax, and unusual pronunciations rarely go unnoticed either, and partners of linguists often lament that what they say is not heard, but rather, how they say it. 3. HYPOTHESIS FORMATION. …

[1]  William Labov,et al.  What is a Linguistic Fact , 1975 .

[2]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  Language and Mind , 1973 .

[3]  Noam Chomsky Current Issues in Linguistic Theory , 1964 .

[4]  F. Gill,et al.  Advice to a Young Scientist , 1982 .

[5]  Philip Carr Linguistic Realities: An Autonomist Metatheory for the Generative Enterprise , 1990 .

[6]  S. Chiat,et al.  Psycholinguistics without ‘psychological reality’ , 1981 .

[7]  John Robert Ross,et al.  Constraints on variables in syntax , 1967 .

[8]  J. Stemberger,et al.  Optimality Theory , 2003 .

[9]  J. Ruscio Clear Thinking with Psychology : Separating Sense from Nonsense , 2001 .

[10]  K. Popper,et al.  Conjectures and refutations;: The growth of scientific knowledge , 1972 .

[11]  Michael B. Kac Grammars and Grammaticality , 1992 .

[12]  Gary James Jason,et al.  The Logic of Scientific Discovery , 1988 .

[13]  Michael B. Kac In defense of autonomous linguistics , 1980 .

[14]  IS LINGUISTICS AN EMPIRICAL SCIENCE , 1976 .

[15]  K. Stanovich How to think straight about psychology , 1985 .

[16]  G. Lakoff The Invariance Hypothesis: is abstract reason based on image-schemas? , 1990 .

[17]  David Eddington,et al.  Spanish epenthesis: Formal and performance perspectives , 2001 .

[18]  James Higginbotham,et al.  Remarks on the metaphysics of linguistics , 1991 .

[19]  W Booth,et al.  Voodoo science. , 1988, Science.

[20]  L. Boroditsky Metaphoric structuring: understanding time through spatial metaphors , 2000, Cognition.

[21]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  Lectures on Government and Binding , 1981 .

[22]  Why cognitive linguists should care more about empirical methods , 2007 .

[23]  Carson T. Schütze The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology , 1998 .

[24]  J. Harnad Trouble with Physics , 2007, 0709.1728.

[25]  J. Katz,et al.  Realism vs. conceptualism in linguistics , 1991 .

[26]  M. Shermer,et al.  Why People Believe Weird Things: Pseudoscience, Superstition, and Other Confusions of Our Time , 1997 .

[27]  Luigi Burzio,et al.  Italian Syntax: A Government-Binding Approach , 1986 .

[28]  K. Pearson The Grammar of Science , 1892, Nature.

[29]  G. Docherty,et al.  Phonological knowledge : conceptual and empirical issues , 2000 .

[30]  John J. Ohala,et al.  There is no interface between phonology and phonetics: a personal view , 1990 .

[31]  Michael K. Tanenhaus,et al.  Processing Reflexives and Pronouns in Picture Noun Phrase , 2006, Cogn. Sci..

[32]  ALEC MARANTZ,et al.  Generative linguistics within the cognitive neuroscience of language , 2005 .

[33]  Esa Itkonen,et al.  Grammatical Theory and Metascience: A critical investigation into the methodological and philosophical foundations of 'autonomous' linguistics , 1978 .

[34]  H. Birx,et al.  The Mismeasure of Man , 1981 .

[35]  K. Popper,et al.  Conjectures and refutations;: The growth of scientific knowledge , 1972 .

[36]  R. Horton Rules and representations , 1993, The Lancet.

[37]  Esa Itkonen Grammatical theory and metascience , 1978 .

[38]  Raymond W. Gibbs,et al.  Introspection and cognitive linguistics: Should we trust our own intuitions? , 2006 .

[39]  Bruce L. Derwing On Drawing the Right Conclusions in Psycholinguistics: Some Critical Areas of Control in Experimental and Analytical Practice , 1983 .

[40]  John Field,et al.  Language and the mind , 1968 .

[41]  G. Lozanov Suggestology and Outlines of Suggestopedy , 1978 .

[42]  Michael B. Kac Autonomous linguistics and psycholinguistics , 1974 .

[43]  Charles Reiss,et al.  Phonology as Cognition , 2000 .

[44]  張奭鎭 Third Texas Conference on Problems of Linguistic Analysis in English , 1966 .

[45]  R. Dirven,et al.  The contested impact of cognitive linguistic research on the psycholinguistics of metaphor understanding , 2006 .

[46]  Mary L. Clayton,et al.  Syllable Structure and Stress in Spanish , 1984 .

[47]  Gerald Holton,et al.  Foundations of modern physical science , 1958 .