Is There A Plausible Theory for Risky Decisions

A large literature is concerned with analysis and empirical application of theories of decision making for environments with risky outcomes. Expected value theory has been known for centuries to be subject to critique by St. Petersburg paradox arguments. More recently, theories of risk aversion have been critiqued with calibration arguments applied to concave payoff transformations. This paper extends the calibration critique to decision theories that represent risk aversion solely with transformation of probabilities. Testable calibration propositions are derived that apply to four representative decision theories: expected utility theory, cumulative prospect theory, rank-dependent expected utility theory, and dual expected utility theory. Heretofore, calibration critiques of theories of risk aversion have been based solely on thought experiments. This paper reports real experiments that provide data on the relevance of the calibration critiques to evaluating the plausibility of theories of risk aversion. The paper also discusses implications of the data for (original) prospect theory with editing of reference payoffs and for the new dual-self model of impulse control. In addition, the paper reports an experiment with a truncated St. Petersburg bet that adds to data inconsistent with risk neutrality.

[1]  James C. Cox,et al.  Risky Decisions in the Large and in the Small:Theory and Experiment , 2008 .

[2]  Christopher C. Rosen,et al.  Measuring Risk Attitudes Controlling for Personality Traits , 2008 .

[3]  Minqiang Li On Aumann and Serrano’s economic index of risk , 2008 .

[4]  M. Rabin,et al.  Reference-Dependent Risk Attitudes , 2007 .

[5]  James C. Cox,et al.  Small- and Large-Stakes Risk Aversion: Implications of Concavity Calibration for Decision Theory , 2005, Games Econ. Behav..

[6]  D. Fudenberg,et al.  A Dual Self Model of Impulse Control , 2004, The American economic review.

[7]  Charles A. Holt,et al.  Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects: New Data without Order Effects , 2005 .

[8]  R. Sugden,et al.  Explaining preference reversal with third-generation prospect theory , 2005 .

[9]  M. Rabin,et al.  A Model of Reference-Dependent Preferences , 2006 .

[10]  Ariel Rubinstein,et al.  Dilemmas of an Economic Theorist , 2006 .

[11]  Eric Johnson,et al.  Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects: Comment , 2004 .

[12]  R. Thaler,et al.  Individual Preferences, Monetary Gambles and the Equity Premium , 2003 .

[13]  Charles A. Holt,et al.  Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects , 2002 .

[14]  William S. Neilson Calibration results for rank-dependent expected utility , 2001 .

[15]  R. Thaler,et al.  Anomalies: Risk Aversion , 2001 .

[16]  M. Rabin Risk Aversion and Expected Utility Theory: A Calibration Theorem , 2000 .

[17]  J. Kagel,et al.  Handbook of Experimental Economics , 1997 .

[18]  J. Quiggin Generalized expected utility theory : the rank-dependent model , 1994 .

[19]  David W Harless,et al.  The predictive utility of generalized expected utility theories , 1994 .

[20]  J. Quiggin Generalized expected utility theory , 1992 .

[21]  A. Tversky,et al.  Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty , 1992 .

[22]  Charles A. Holt,et al.  Introduction to Experimental Economics , 1992 .

[23]  Colin Camerer Behavioral Game Theory , 1990 .

[24]  M. Yaari The Dual Theory of Choice under Risk , 1987 .

[25]  J. Quiggin A theory of anticipated utility , 1982 .

[26]  Preferences Scientific Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. , 1982 .

[27]  A. Tversky,et al.  Prospect theory: analysis of decision under risk , 1979 .

[28]  D. Bernoulli Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis : translated into German and English , 1967 .

[29]  D. Bernoulli Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk , 1954 .

[30]  E. Rowland Theory of Games and Economic Behavior , 1946, Nature.