Many natural languages use prepositions to mark relations between entities of various kinds – between physical entities and their spatial locations, between temporal entities and their temporal locations, between abstract entities of various kinds (e.g. between ideas and their ‘mental locations’). In the current paper I will show that the consequences of using prepositions to relate temporal entities emerge naturally from the basic interpretations of the prepositions themselves together with a very weak logic of events, where I take it that prepositions denote abstract relations whose significance only emerges when properties of the related items are taken into consideration. 1 Prepositions as abstract relations “in: preposition expressing inclusion or position within limits of space, time, circumstance, etc.” Pocket Oxford Dictionary of Current English, 1970 Consider the following sets of sentences: (1) a. He drove from London to Paris.1 b. He drove from dawn to dusk. (1a) to (1c) are taken from [Dowty, 1979]. c. He copied it from his hard drive to a floppy. d. I got the RAE results from the Guardian2. (2) a. I saw a man in the park. b. I saw him in January. c. I’ve got an idea for a paper about time in my mind, but I don’t know how it will work out. d. I’ve got 230 people in my AI class next term. (3) a. I saw him at the station. b. I saw him at two o’clock. c. He seemed to be at his wits’ end. All of these, apart perhaps from the very last one, seem to be entirely natural. The prepositions that appear in them, however, clearly link very different kinds of things. In the (a) examples the ground for the relation denoted by the PP is a physical location, in the (b) examples it is a temporal location, in the (c) and (d) examples it seems to be some sort of abstract entity. Is one of these relations primary, with the others as some kind of metaphorical extension, or is there some common element which gets extended in different ways depending on the nature of the ground? This is not, in this paper, a question about the history of prepositions, either over the evolution of the language across the centuries or within each language learner. It may be that, at least historically, the spatial interpretations of some of these prepositions come first, but there is very little evidence that the spatial readings predominate in the language as because they ranked UMIST higher than anyone else did!
[1]
Allan Ramsay,et al.
Theorem Proving for Untyped Constructive $\lambda$-Calculus: Implementation and Application
,
2001,
Log. J. IGPL.
[2]
Michael Kohlhase,et al.
Inference and Computational Semantics
,
2004,
J. Log. Lang. Inf..
[3]
Alice G. B. ter Meulen,et al.
Representing Time in Natural Language: The Dynamic Interpretation of Tense and Aspect
,
1995
.
[4]
H. Keisler.
Foundations of infinitesimal calculus
,
1976
.
[5]
Claire Gardent,et al.
Interpreting Definites using Model Generation
,
2000
.
[6]
James Pustejovsky,et al.
The Generative Lexicon
,
1995,
CL.
[7]
David R. Dowty,et al.
Word Meaning and Montague Grammar
,
1979
.
[8]
Carlota S. Smith,et al.
The Parameter of Aspect
,
1991
.
[9]
Elisa Bertino,et al.
A temporal object-oriented data model with multiple granularities
,
1999,
Proceedings. Sixth International Workshop on Temporal Representation and Reasoning. TIME-99.
[10]
Mehmet A. Orgun,et al.
Dealing with Multiple Granularity of Time in Temporal Logic Programming
,
1996,
J. Symb. Comput..
[11]
Ray Turner,et al.
A theory of properties
,
1987,
Journal of Symbolic Logic.
[12]
Allan Ramsay,et al.
Theorem proving for untyped constructive λ-calculus : implementation and application
,
2001
.
[13]
Manfred Pinkal,et al.
An Education and Research Tool for Computational Semantics
,
1996,
COLING.
[14]
Mark Steedman,et al.
Temporal Ontology and Temporal Reference
,
1988,
CL.
[15]
Michael Kühn,et al.
Abducing Coreference by Model Construction
,
2007
.
[16]
L. Elton,et al.
THE DIRECTION OF TIME
,
1978
.