Derivational Order in Syntax : Evidence and Architectural Consequences *

generative grammars have traditionally been studied under the assumption that they are implementation independent. It is assumed, for example, that eventually we will be able to write software or build hardware to implement the human language system in computers that differ from human ‘hardware’ in many respects. As such, this is taken as evidence for implementation independence. This, however, is clearly an empirical question. It is a real and attractive possibility that computational modelers of the future might succeed in that effort, but it is far from having been accomplished at this time. The fact that some grammars that approximate fragments of human language have been digitally implemented does not settle the question. A relevant model should minimally be completely descriptively adequate, and one might reasonably want the model to approximate human linguistic abilities in more ways than simply classifying (un)acceptable sentences. Such models currently inhabit the realm of thought experiments. Here we disagree with Neeleman & van de Koot (2010), who agree with us on the importance of implementation (in)dependence, but take it as quite significant that some natural language grammars could be implemented in different artificial devices, concluding that human language is implementation independent. In the meantime, we argue that the emphasis on the implementation independence of generative grammars is misplaced if the purpose of the endeavor is to understand the nature of the human system. If a research community makes the choice to carve out one sub-area of the study of human language abilities, e.g., classifying (un)acceptable sentences, and then finds that this sub-area can be described in implementation independent terms, then this surely does not entail that the sub-area corresponds to a privileged, implementation independent sub-area of the human language faculty. There is no doubt that it is interesting and useful to develop explicit computational models of human language, but such models cannot show whether human grammatical abilities are, in fact, independent of their cognitive or neural implementation. Regardless of what one’s personal hunch is about the likelihood of successful non-human implementation of language, a more interesting question for our purposes is whether it is implementation independent within humans. According to the standard formulation of the principled extensionalist view, speakers of a language have knowledge of the (un)acceptable sentences of their language, and this knowledge can be described at an abstract level by a generative grammar. Importantly, it is assumed that this abstract knowledge is implementation independent, and that speakers can put their knowledge to use in different ways in activities such as speaking, understanding, and internally generated speech. This means that for any given well-formed sentence structure defined by the grammar a speaker may have a number of different ways of mentally assembling the structure. If this assumption is supported, then the principled extensionalist is justified in separating speakers' knowledge of what is well formed from their knowledge of how to assemble wellformed structures. But if speakers do not, in fact, have multiple ways of constructing 2 Neeleman and van de Koot describe a thought experiment in which a pair of computers with radically different underlying architectures are both able to pass a kind of Turing Test for human language, such that their performance is indistinguishable from human native speakers of the language. They argue that one would want to say that both computers speak the relevant language, and conclude that this is because the computers and the humans would share an abstract, implementation-independent grammar. We agree with the intuition behind this thought experiment, but it seems to reveal more about the common usage of predicates like “speaks French” than about the nature of the human language faculty. Despite this misgiving, we find much to like about Neeleman and van de Koot’s discussion of the challenges involved in understanding grammatical theories at different levels of description. Derivational order in syntax Colin Phillips & Shevaun Lewis 16 the same representations, then human language appears to be more implementation dependent. The evidence on whether speakers have multiple ways of constructing the same sentence representation is not extensive, but there are a number of reasons to think that speakers have one and only one way of assembling any individual representation. There is almost no evidence for the alternative view that speakers have multiple ways of building the same representation. First, speaking and understanding proceed in the same (roughly) left-to-right fashion. Although they have different goals, they have a great deal in common, appear to construct the same representations, and plausibly do so in the same order, although this topic has not been investigated in great detail. Second, in comprehension and production there is much evidence that speakers build structures and interpretations incrementally, in roughly the order in which words are presented. We are unaware of evidence that speakers are able to construct the same interpretation in different orders. For example, reading backwards is a task that lies somewhere in the difficult-to-impossible range, despite its correspondence with the derivational order assumed in many generative grammars. Third, in cases of reanalysis in sentence understanding, where comprehenders are led into a ‘garden path’ and must then reorganize their initial parse, some evidence suggests that speakers repair by returning to the error point and simply re-parsing the sentence in exactly the same order that it was presented (Inoue & Fodor, 1995; Grodner et al., 2003). We therefore adopt the working hypothesis that natural language grammars are implementation dependent with respect to how sentences are assembled: there is only one algorithm for structure-building across all human speakers (of the same language). We would certainly welcome more systematic evidence, but currently the evidence for the alternative implementation independent position is practically non-existent. The implementation dependent position is the simpler and more falsifiable hypothesis, and hence should be preferred until proven otherwise. Consequently, we think that the principled extensionalist position is unwarranted, and that the motivations for developing abstract generative grammars are more pragmatic than principled. We have no problems with pragmatic motivations, and we recognize the value of focusing on characterizing good/bad sentences as a way of making headway in describing human language. But this is very different from the position that the characterization of good/bad sentences is a fundamentally separate enterprise from understanding realtime language processes. Ultimately we seek theories that capture how sentences are put together, and not just what their final form is. In discussions of these issues we sometimes encounter an objection in the form of a 'slippery slope' argument. If human language is better described in terms of real time cognitive processes rather than abstract functions, so the argument runs, then why stop there – why not continue all the way down to the level of neurochemical processes in brain cells or beyond? As with other slippery slope arguments, the expectation is that we should find this consequence appalling, and hence should drop the entire argument. We acknowledge the concern, but disagree with this argument. First, we are not arguing against the usefulness of abstract descriptions in the study of language. We find them exceedingly useful. We are simply arguing that there is no privileged level of abstraction – the level occupied by most current generative grammars – that is 3 Although we have focused our attention here on the interpretation of derivational grammatical theories, the issue of implementation (in)dependence is equally relevant to interpreting grammatical theories that assume no derivations. Non-derivational syntactic theories, which are often presented as preferable due to their order-neutrality, imply implementation independence. If syntactic representations are not, in fact, implementation independent, then that should count against nonderivational theories, just as it counts against bottom-to-top derivations. STiL – Studies in Linguistics Vol. 6 17 exempt from considerations of psychological implementation. Second, it should be emphasized that implementation (in)dependence is not an all-or-nothing property of an abstract system. Rather, a system's implementation (in)dependence must be evaluated at each successive degree of abstraction. Our focus in the current discussion is on the relation between symbolic descriptions of the structure of sentences and symbolic descriptions of the procedures for assembling sentences in real time. This leaves open the possibility that human language is implementation independent at a lower level. For example, there are interesting arguments that the basic notion of hierarchical structure in language must be implementation independent with respect to its neural encoding, because of the very different demands of immediate vs. long-term encoding of sentences in memory (Jackendoff, 2002; van der Velde & de Kamps, 2006). Briefly, the most plausible method for long-term information storage in the brain – through changes in synaptic connectivity – is too slow for the millisecondscale processes needed for real-time language use. The need for dual encodings of the same structures suggests that structured representations are not always neurally encoded in the same fashion, and hence that they are implementation independent. It is far from certain that this argument goes through, because it is not clear that immediate and long-term encodings of sentences in memory are genuinely iso

[1]  M. B. Emeneau Foundations of Language. Louis H. Gray , 1940 .

[2]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. , 1966 .

[3]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  Topics in the Theory of Generative Grammar , 1966 .

[4]  G. Seth Psychology of Language , 1968, Nature.

[5]  Willem J. M. Levelt,et al.  Hierarchical chunking in sentence processing , 1970 .

[6]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  Deep structure, surface structure, and semantic interpretation , 1969 .

[7]  Thomas G. Bever,et al.  The underlying structures of sentences are the primary units of immediate speech processing , 1969 .

[8]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  Conditions on transformations , 1971 .

[9]  Willem J. M. Levelt,et al.  Formal grammars in linguistics and psycholinguistics , 1974 .

[10]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  Lectures on Government and Binding , 1981 .

[11]  Tim Stowell,et al.  Origins of phrase structure , 1981 .

[12]  Esther Torrego Salcedo On inversion in Spanish and some of its effects , 1984 .

[13]  Mark Steedman,et al.  Dependency and Coordination in the Grammar of Dutch and English , 1985 .

[14]  Robert Freidin,et al.  Fundamental Issues in the Theory of Binding , 1986 .

[15]  J. K. Bock Syntactic persistence in language production , 1986, Cognitive Psychology.

[16]  Laurie A. Stowe,et al.  Parsing WH-constructions: Evidence for on-line gap location , 1986 .

[17]  Lyn Frazier,et al.  Sentence processing: A tutorial review. , 1987 .

[18]  David R. Dowty Type Raising, Functional Composition, and Non-Constituent Conjunction , 1988 .

[19]  Kathryn Bock,et al.  Closed-class immanence in sentence production , 1989, Cognition.

[20]  D Swinney,et al.  The role of structure in coreference assignment during sentence comprehension , 1989, Journal of psycholinguistic research.

[21]  K. Bock,et al.  Framing sentences , 1990, Cognition.

[22]  M. Garrett,et al.  Syntactically Based Sentence Processing Classes: Evidence from Event-Related Brain Potentials , 1991, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience.

[23]  Noam Chomsky A minimalist program for linguistic theory , 1992 .

[24]  M. Garman Psycholinguistics , 1992 .

[25]  P. Holcomb,et al.  Event-related brain potentials elicited by syntactic anomaly , 1992 .

[26]  Colin M. Brown,et al.  The syntactic positive shift (sps) as an erp measure of syntactic processing , 1993 .

[27]  Robert Kluender,et al.  Subjacency as a processing phenomenon , 1993 .

[28]  M. Pickering,et al.  Dependency categorial grammar and coordination , 1993 .

[29]  A. Friederici,et al.  Event-related brain potentials during natural speech processing: effects of semantic, morphological and syntactic violations. , 1993, Brain research. Cognitive brain research.

[30]  C.-T. James Huang,et al.  Reconstruction and the structure of VP: some theoretical consequences , 1993 .

[31]  Maryellen C. MacDonald,et al.  The lexical nature of syntactic ambiguity resolution , 1994 .

[32]  Mark S. Seidenberg,et al.  The lexical nature of syntactic ambiguity resolution [corrected]. , 1994, Psychological review.

[33]  A. Inoue,et al.  Information-paced parsing of Japanese , 1995 .

[34]  R. Mazuka Can Japanese speakers be led down the garden-path? , 1995 .

[35]  John A. Hawkins,et al.  A Performance Theory of Order and Constituency , 1995 .

[36]  C. Heycock Asymmetries in reconstruction , 1995 .

[37]  D. Lightfoot The View from Building 20: Essays in Linguistics in Honor of Sylvain Bromberger , 1995 .

[38]  Yuji Takano Predicate fronting and internal subjects , 1995 .

[39]  M. Pickering,et al.  Plausibility and the Processing of Unbounded Dependencies:An Eye-Tracking Study , 1996 .

[40]  Colin Phillips,et al.  Order and structure , 1996 .

[41]  Shelia M. Kennison,et al.  Reading the WordsHer, His, Him:Implications for Parsing Principles Based on Frequency and on Structure , 1997 .

[42]  Mark Steedman,et al.  Surface structure and interpretation , 1996, Linguistic inquiry.

[43]  J. Zwart The Minimalist Program , 1998, Journal of Linguistics.

[44]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  Minimalist inquiries : the framework , 1998 .

[45]  Ken Safir,et al.  Vehicle Change and Reconstruction in -Chains , 1999, Linguistic Inquiry.

[46]  P. Schlenker La flexion de l'adjectif en allemand : La morphologie de haut en bas : La linéarité , 1999 .

[47]  Lyn Frazier,et al.  Feature manipulation in sentence comprehension: 2703 , 1999 .

[48]  P. J. Meijer,et al.  Building Syntactic Structure in Speaking , 1999, Journal of psycholinguistic research.

[49]  N. Richards Dependency Formation and Directionality of Tree Construction , 1999 .

[50]  Susan M. Garnsey,et al.  Agreement Processes in Sentence Comprehension , 1999 .

[51]  D. Fox Reconstruction, Binding Theory, and the Interpretation of Chains , 1999, Linguistic Inquiry.

[52]  N. Hornstein Move! : a minimalist theory of construal , 2000 .

[53]  David Lebeaux,et al.  Language acquisition and the form of the grammar , 2000 .

[54]  Dov M. Gabbay,et al.  Dynamic syntax - the flow of language understanding , 2000 .

[55]  Chris Wilder,et al.  Right Node Raising and the LCA , 2000 .

[56]  Thomas G. Bever,et al.  Sentence Comprehension: The Integration of Habits and Rules , 2001 .

[57]  Jason Merchant,et al.  The syntax of silence : sluicing, islands, and the theory of ellipsis , 2001 .

[58]  Cedric Boeckx,et al.  Scope Reconstruction And A-Movement , 2001 .

[59]  A. Hollingworth,et al.  Thematic Roles Assigned along the Garden Path Linger , 2001, Cognitive Psychology.

[60]  W. Badecker,et al.  The processing role of structural constraints on the interpretation of pronouns and anaphors. , 2002, Journal of experimental psychology. Learning, memory, and cognition.

[61]  Elizabeth Bates,et al.  Clausal backgrounding and pronominal reference: A functionalist approach to c-command , 2002 .

[62]  Peter Hagoort,et al.  How the brain solves the binding problem for language: a neurocomputational model of syntactic processing , 2003, NeuroImage.

[63]  Winfried Lechner,et al.  Phrase structure paradoxes, movement and ellipsis , 2003 .

[64]  P. Sturt,et al.  The time-course of the application of binding constraints in reference resolution , 2003 .

[65]  Fernanda Ferreira,et al.  The misinterpretation of noncanonical sentences , 2003, Cognitive Psychology.

[66]  C. Phillips Linear Order and Constituency , 2003, Linguistic Inquiry.

[67]  Mark Baltin,et al.  The Interaction of Ellipsis and Binding: Implications for the Sequencing of Principle A , 2003 .

[68]  Vered Argaman,et al.  Against Repair-Based Reanalysis in Sentence Comprehension , 2003, Journal of psycholinguistic research.

[69]  C. Phillips Linguistics and Linking Problems , 2003 .

[70]  Shelia M. Kennison,et al.  Comprehending the pronouns her, him, and his: Implications for theories of referential processing☆ , 2003 .

[71]  S. Warren,et al.  Developmental language disorders : from phenotypes to etiologies , 2004 .

[72]  A. Weinberg,et al.  Processing filler-gap dependencies in a head-final language , 2004 .

[73]  Maximiliano Guimaraes Miranda Derivation and Representation of Syntactic Amalgams , 2004 .

[74]  Myung-Kwan Park When Things are Cumulated or Distributed Across Coordinate Conjuncts , 2005 .

[75]  Die Lücken im Bild von der 'Subjektlücken'-Koordination , 2005 .

[76]  Ora Matushansky,et al.  Recherches linguistiques de Vincennes , 2005 .

[77]  Ronnie Cann,et al.  The Dynamics of Language: An Introduction. Syntax and Semantics. Volume 35. , 2005 .

[78]  William O'Grady,et al.  Syntactic Carpentry: An Emergentist Approach to Syntax , 2005 .

[79]  Jason Merchant,et al.  Fragments and ellipsis , 2005 .

[80]  Katherine A. DeLong,et al.  Probabilistic word pre-activation during language comprehension inferred from electrical brain activity , 2005, Nature Neuroscience.

[81]  Douglas Saddy,et al.  Processing Negative Polarity Items: When Negation Comes Through the Backdoor , 2005 .

[82]  F. van der Velde,et al.  Neural blackboard architectures of combinatorial structures in cognition , 2006, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[83]  Nicolas Guilliot A top-down analysis for reconstruction , 2006 .

[84]  Cedric Boeckx Understanding Minimalist Syntax: Lessons from Locality in Long-Distance Dependencies , 2006 .

[85]  Michael K. Tanenhaus,et al.  Processing Reflexives and Pronouns in Picture Noun Phrase , 2006, Cogn. Sci..

[86]  Ellen F. Lau,et al.  The role of structural prediction in rapid syntactic analysis , 2006, Brain and Language.

[87]  Christian Barker,et al.  Explaining Crossover and Superiority as Left-to-right Evaluation , 2006 .

[88]  M. Baltin The Nonunity of VP-Preposing , 2006 .

[89]  C. Phillips The Real-Time Status of Island Phenomena , 2007 .

[90]  Joseph Sabbagh,et al.  Ordering and linearizing rightward movement , 2007 .

[91]  Patrick Sturt,et al.  Semantic re-interpretation and garden path recovery , 2007, Cognition.

[92]  Cristiano Chesi,et al.  FIVE REASONS FOR BUILDING PHRASE STRUCTURES TOP-DOWN FROM LEFT TO RIGHT * , 2007 .

[93]  Ellen F. Lau,et al.  The effect of syntactic constraints on the processing of backwards anaphora , 2007 .

[94]  Angela D. Friederici,et al.  Mapping sentence form onto meaning: The syntax–semantic interface , 2007, Brain Research.

[95]  Idan Landau,et al.  Constraints on Partial VP‐fronting , 2007 .

[96]  Fernanda Ferreira,et al.  The 'Good Enough' Approach to Language Comprehension , 2007, Lang. Linguistics Compass.

[97]  Ellen F. Lau,et al.  A cortical network for semantics: (de)constructing the N400 , 2008, Nature Reviews Neuroscience.

[98]  John J. McCarthy,et al.  Optimality-Theoretic Syntax , 2008 .

[99]  M. Pickering,et al.  Structural priming: a critical review. , 2008, Psychological bulletin.

[100]  Paul D. Elbourne Ellipsis Sites as Definite Descriptions , 2008, Linguistic Inquiry.

[101]  K. Shiobara Prosodic Phase and Left-to-Right Structure Building , 2008 .

[102]  Kara D. Federmeier,et al.  Chapter 1 Time for Meaning: Electrophysiology Provides Insights into the Dynamics of Representation and Processing in Semantic Memory , 2009 .

[103]  Ellen F. Lau,et al.  Agreement Attraction in Comprehension: Representations and Processes. , 2009 .

[104]  Ellen Frances Lau The predictive nature of language comprehension , 2009 .

[105]  C. Phillips,et al.  Illusory licensing effects across dependency types: ERP evidence , 2009, Brain and Language.

[106]  Colin Phillips,et al.  Multiple dependencies and the role of the grammar in real-time comprehension1 , 2009, Journal of Linguistics.

[107]  Masaya Yoshida,et al.  Incremental Processing of Coreference and Binding in Japanese , 2009 .

[108]  Jan-Wouter Zwart,et al.  Prospects for top-down derivation , 2009 .

[109]  Philip Hofmeister,et al.  Cognitive Constraints on Syntactic Islands , 2009 .

[110]  Kyle Johnson,et al.  Gapping Is Not (VP-) Ellipsis , 2009, Linguistic Inquiry.

[111]  Mats Wirén,et al.  Syntactic Parsing , 2010, Handbook of Natural Language Processing.

[112]  D. Poeppel,et al.  The linguistic processes underlying the P600 , 2010 .

[113]  Hans van de Koot,et al.  Theoretical Validity and Psychological Reality of the Grammatical Code , 2010 .

[114]  James McCloskey,et al.  Resumptive pronouns, A-binding,and levels of representations in Irish , 2011 .

[115]  James McCloskey,et al.  SLUICING ( : ) BETWEEN STRUCTURE AND INFERENCE * , 2011 .

[116]  Colin Phillips,et al.  5: Grammatical Illusions and Selective Fallibility in Real-Time Language Comprehension , 2011 .

[117]  Hartmut Fitz,et al.  Getting real about Semantic Illusions: Rethinking the functional role of the P600 in language comprehension , 2012, Brain Research.

[118]  Bradley Larson,et al.  A Dilemma with Accounts of Right Node Raising , 2012, Linguistic Inquiry.

[119]  Jon Sprouse,et al.  A test of the relation between working-memory capacity and syntactic island effects , 2012 .

[120]  Colin Phillips,et al.  Structural constraints on pronoun resolution : Distinguishing early and late sensitivity to illicit antecedents , 2012 .

[121]  C. Phillips Some arguments and nonarguments for reductionist accounts of syntactic phenomena , 2013 .

[122]  M. Tanenhaus Afterword The impact of “The cognitive basis for linguistic structures” , 2013 .

[123]  Colin Phillips Experimental Syntax and Island Effects: On the nature of island constraints I: Language processing and reductionist accounts , 2013 .

[124]  P. Grosz Movement and Agreement in Right-Node-Raising Constructions , 2015 .