Cognitive Success: A Consequentialist Account of Rationality in Cognition

One of the most discussed issues in psychology-presently and in the past-is how to define and measure the extent to which human cognition is rational. The rationality of human cognition is often evaluated in terms of normative standards based on a priori intuitions. Yet this approach has been challenged by two recent developments in psychology that we review in this article: ecological rationality and descriptivism. Going beyond these contributions, we consider it a good moment for psychologists and philosophers to join forces and work toward a new foundation for the definition of rational cognition. We take a first step in this direction by proposing that the rationality of both cognitive and normative systems can be measured in terms of their cognitive success. Cognitive success can be defined and gauged in terms of two factors: ecological validity (the system's validity in conditions in which it is applicable) and the system's applicability (the scope of conditions under which it can be applied). As we show, prominent systems of reasoning-deductive reasoning, Bayesian reasoning, uncertain conditionals, and prediction and choice-perform rather differently on these two factors. Furthermore, we demonstrate that conceptualizing rationality according to its cognitive success offers a new perspective on the time-honored relationship between the descriptive ("is") and the normative ("ought") in psychology and philosophy.

[1]  J. Platt Strong Inference: Certain systematic methods of scientific thinking may produce much more rapid progress than others. , 1964, Science.

[2]  P C Wason,et al.  Regression in reasoning? , 1969, British journal of psychology.

[3]  B. Love,et al.  The myth of computational level theory and the vacuity of rational analysis , 2011, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[4]  Ralph Hertwig,et al.  Abnormality, rationality, and sanity , 2013, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[5]  Charles Kemp,et al.  How to Grow a Mind: Statistics, Structure, and Abstraction , 2011, Science.

[6]  Ralph Hertwig,et al.  The conjunction fallacy and the many meanings of and , 2008, Cognition.

[7]  Gerhard Schurz,et al.  No Free Lunch Theorem, Inductive Skepticism, and the Optimality of Meta-induction , 2017, Philosophy of Science.

[8]  G. Gigerenzer On Narrow Norms and Vague Heuristics: A Reply to Kahneman and Tversky (1996) , 1996 .

[9]  John W. Payne,et al.  The adaptive decision maker: Name index , 1993 .

[10]  Richard Pettigrew,et al.  An Objective Justification of Bayesianism I: Measuring Inaccuracy* , 2010, Philosophy of Science.

[11]  Ulrike Hahn,et al.  Normative theories of argumentation: are some norms better than others? , 2012, Synthese.

[12]  Gerd Gigerenzer,et al.  Deductive competence: A desert devoid of content and context , 1997 .

[13]  P. Wason On the Failure to Eliminate Hypotheses in a Conceptual Task , 1960 .

[14]  Gerhard Schurz,et al.  The Is-Ought Problem: An Investigation in Philosophical Logic , 1997 .

[15]  Paul D. Thorn,et al.  REWARD VERSUS RISK IN UNCERTAIN INFERENCE: THEOREMS AND SIMULATIONS , 2012, The Review of Symbolic Logic.

[16]  Jan K. Woike,et al.  The Robust Beauty of Heuristics in Choice under Uncertainty , 2019, Taming Uncertainty.

[17]  John R. Anderson Is human cognition adaptive? , 1991, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[18]  Paul D. Thorn,et al.  Qualitative probabilistic inference under varied entropy levels , 2016, J. Appl. Log..

[19]  Shira Elqayam Grounded rationality: Descriptivism in epistemic context , 2012, Synthese.

[20]  Paul D. Thorn,et al.  A Utility Based Evaluation of Logico-probabilistic Systems , 2014, Stud Logica.

[21]  Nick Chater,et al.  A rational analysis of the selection task as optimal data selection. , 1994 .

[22]  H. Simon,et al.  Invariants of human behavior. , 1990, Annual review of psychology.

[23]  N. Chater,et al.  The probabilistic approach to human reasoning , 2001, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[24]  S. Sloman,et al.  Base-rate respect: From ecological rationality to dual processes. , 2007, The Behavioral and brain sciences.

[25]  Leonidas Spiliopoulos,et al.  Strategic Uncertainty and Incomplete Information: The Homo Heuristicus Does Not Fold , 2019, Taming Uncertainty.

[26]  David Shier,et al.  CAN HUMAN RATIONALITY BE DEFENDED A PRIORI , 2000 .

[27]  L. Beach,et al.  Man as an Intuitive Statistician , 2022 .

[28]  Gerd Gigerenzer,et al.  How bad is incoherence , 2016 .

[29]  Gerd Gigerenzer,et al.  Homo Heuristicus: Why Biased Minds Make Better Inferences , 2009, Top. Cogn. Sci..

[30]  David E. Over,et al.  Editorial: From Is to Ought: The Place of Normative Models in the Study of Human Thought , 2016, Front. Psychol..

[31]  James Hawthorne,et al.  The Quantitative/Qualitative Watershed for Rules of Uncertain Inference , 2007, Stud Logica.

[32]  Gerd Gigerenzer,et al.  The "conjunction fallacy" revisited : How intelligent inferences look like reasoning errors , 1999 .

[33]  Ulrike Hahn,et al.  The Problem of Circularity in Evidence, Argument, and Explanation , 2011, Perspectives on psychological science : a journal of the Association for Psychological Science.

[34]  Julian N. Marewski,et al.  Cognitive niches: an ecological model of strategy selection. , 2011, Psychological review.

[35]  Wesley C. Salmon,et al.  Should we attempt to justify induction? , 1957 .

[36]  L. Cohen Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated? , 1981, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[37]  A. Tversky,et al.  Subjective Probability: A Judgment of Representativeness , 1972 .

[38]  J. Tenenbaum,et al.  Optimal Predictions in Everyday Cognition , 2006, Psychological science.

[39]  H. Leitgeb,et al.  An Objective Justification of Bayesianism II: The Consequences of Minimizing Inaccuracy* , 2010, Philosophy of Science.

[40]  David H. Wolpert,et al.  The Lack of A Priori Distinctions Between Learning Algorithms , 1996, Neural Computation.

[41]  I. Kant,et al.  Critique of Pure Reason: Remark to the amphiboly of concepts of reflection , 1998 .

[42]  Gerhard Schurz,et al.  Optimality justifications: new foundations for foundation-oriented epistemology , 2017, Synthese.

[43]  G. Brier VERIFICATION OF FORECASTS EXPRESSED IN TERMS OF PROBABILITY , 1950 .

[44]  L. Cosmides The logic of social exchange: Has natural selection shaped how humans reason? Studies with the Wason selection task , 1989, Cognition.

[45]  Paul D. Thorn,et al.  The Revenge of Ecological Rationality: Strategy-Selection by Meta-Induction Within Changing Environments , 2015, Minds and Machines.

[46]  Gerhard Schurz,et al.  Cognitive success: instrumental justifications of normative systems of reasoning , 2014, Front. Psychol..

[47]  Karel Lambert,et al.  Outline of a theory of scientific understanding , 1994, Synthese.

[48]  Jonathan Evans,et al.  Norms for reasoning about decisions , 2011, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[49]  D. Kahneman Maps of Bounded Rationality: Psychology for Behavioral Economics , 2003 .

[50]  S. Stich,et al.  Ending the Rationality Wars: How to Make Disputes About Human Rationality Disappear , 2002 .

[51]  P. C. Wason,et al.  The Processing of Positive and Negative Information , 1959 .

[52]  Ralph Hertwig,et al.  The robust beauty of ordinary information. , 2010, Psychological review.

[53]  G Gigerenzer,et al.  Reasoning the fast and frugal way: models of bounded rationality. , 1996, Psychological review.

[54]  Renée Elio,et al.  What Should Default Reasoning be, by Default? , 1997, Comput. Intell..

[55]  Jeff B. Paris,et al.  When Maximizing Entropy gives the Rational Closure , 2003, J. Log. Comput..

[56]  Lola L. Lopes The Rhetoric of Irrationality , 1991 .