The Optimization Research Program: Studying Adaptations by Their Function

We develop as a scientific research program (sensu Lakatos, 1978) the essential assumptions used in applying optimization techniques to the study of adaptation. The assumptions and hypotheses of the research program are of two kinds: (1) hard core and (2) strategic. Any prediction is derived from a conjuction of both hard-core and strategic hypothesis. The hard-core hypotheses define evolution as the change in the frequencies of strategies (rather than, for example, alleles or genotypes). Consequently, fitness is a property of strategies rather than genetic entities or individuals. Strategic hypotheses describe how a strategy's fitness depends on various inputs (e.g., mating success and energetic intake), and on how the feasible set of inputs to fitness is constrained. Strategies are described as being supervenient (sensu Rosenberg, 1985) on genotypes because while a given genotype specifies a strategy, a given strategy does not specify any finite set of genotypes. The supervenience of strategies lends credence to functional explanations of the occurrence of strategies. In the Optimization Research Program the function of a strategy is functional only in that it influences the per-capita growth rate of the strategy. A refuted prediction leads to modifying the strategic hypotheses rather that the hard-core ones. In a progressive research program, the new, modified hypotheses avoid being characterized as ad hoc by virtue of the fact that they can generate new testable predictions. Lakatos proposed that science progresses through a competition between different research programs as defined by their hard cores. We suggest that alternative hard cores might include the assumption of studies in quantitave genetics to the effect that genetics generally constrain adaptation at an evolutionarily stable equilibrium.

[1]  R. Punnett,et al.  The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection , 1930, Nature.

[2]  H. Grüneberg,et al.  Introduction to quantitative genetics , 1960 .

[3]  T. Kuhn,et al.  The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. , 1964 .

[4]  Kiyoshi Asano,et al.  On the theory of , 1968 .

[5]  J. M. Smith,et al.  The Logic of Animal Conflict , 1973, Nature.

[6]  H. Pulliam,et al.  On the Theory of Optimal Diets , 1974, The American Naturalist.

[7]  H. Pulliam Diet Optimization with Nutrient Constraints , 1975, The American Naturalist.

[8]  H. Putnam Mathematics, Matter, And Method , 1975 .

[9]  J M Smith,et al.  Evolution and the theory of games , 1976 .

[10]  I. Lakatos Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes , 1976 .

[11]  J. M. Smith,et al.  Optimization Theory in Evolution , 1978 .

[12]  G. Belovsky,et al.  Diet optimization in a generalist herbivore: the moose. , 1978, Theoretical population biology.

[13]  R. Hughes Optimal Diets under the Energy Maximization Premise: The Effects of Recognition Time and Learning , 1979, The American Naturalist.

[14]  S. Gould,et al.  The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme , 1979, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B. Biological Sciences.

[15]  J. Ollason Learning to forage--optimally? , 1980, Theoretical population biology.

[16]  John R. Krebs,et al.  Optimal Foraging and Cryptic Prey , 1980 .

[17]  W. Newton-Smith The rationality of science , 1983 .

[18]  R. Lande,et al.  A Quantitative Genetic Theory of Life History Evolution , 1982 .

[19]  S. Gould,et al.  Exaptation—a Missing Term in the Science of Form , 1982, Paleobiology.

[20]  K. Waddington Optimal diet theory: sequential and simultaneous encounter models. , 1982 .

[21]  E. Mayr How to Carry Out the Adaptationist Program? , 1983, The American Naturalist.

[22]  John W. Glasser Is Conventional Foraging Theory Optimal? , 1984, The American Naturalist.

[23]  G. Pyke Optimal Foraging Theory: A Critical Review , 1984 .

[24]  T. Vincent,et al.  Stability in an evolutionary game , 1984 .

[25]  G. A. Clark,et al.  Perspectives in Ornithology , 1984 .

[26]  A. Grafen Natural selection, kin selection and group selection [Polistes fuscatus, wasps] , 1984 .

[27]  R. O'Grady Evolutionary theory and teleology. , 1984, Journal of theoretical biology.

[28]  Central-Place Foraging: Some Aspects of Prey Choice for Multiple-Prey Loaders , 1985, The American Naturalist.

[29]  M. Kirkpatrick Evolution of Female Choice and Male Parental Investment in Polygynous Species: The Demise of the "Sexy Son" , 1985, The American Naturalist.

[30]  Alexander Rosenberg,et al.  The structure of biological science , 1986 .

[31]  S. L. Lima,et al.  Foraging-efficiency-predation-risk trade-off in the grey squirrel , 1985, Animal Behaviour.

[32]  I. Jamieson The Functional Approach to Behavior: Is it Useful? , 1986, The American Naturalist.

[33]  J. Rutledge,et al.  Quantitative Genetics in Natural Plant Populations: A Review of the Theory , 1986, The American Naturalist.

[34]  T. Mitchell-Olds QUANTITATIVE GENETICS OF SURVIVAL AND GROWTH IN IMPATIENS CAPENSIS , 1986, Evolution; international journal of organic evolution.

[35]  S. L. Lima,et al.  Influence of predation risk on diet selection: a simple example in the grey squirrel , 1986, Animal Behaviour.

[36]  R. Bürger CONSTRAINTS FOR THE EVOLUTION OF FUNCTIONALLY COUPLED CHARACTERS: A NONLINEAR ANALYSIS OF A PHENOTYPIC MODEL , 1986, Evolution; international journal of organic evolution.

[37]  S. Stearns,et al.  Evolutionary Insights Should Not Be Wasted , 1987 .

[38]  T. Vincent,et al.  A theory for the evolutionary game , 1987 .

[39]  R. Gray Faith and foraging: a critique of the "paradigm argument from design" , 1987 .

[40]  W. Mitchell Informational constraints on optimally foraging hummingbirds , 1989 .