The Presocratic Philosophers

cannot be neither nor nonfor every value of . Aristotle, it need hardly be said, was well aware of this (cf., e.g., GC 329a10). But if the ‘unlimited’ was not entirely characterless, what was its character? In several passages Aristotle talks of phusiologoi who took as their principle a stuff ‘between’ (metaxu) the other elements; and he probably had Anaximander in mind. According to some scholars, Theophrastus thought that Anaximander’s principle was a ‘mixture’ (migma) of all stuffs. These passages are all controversial, but one thing is fairly clear: if the Peripatetics did actually ascribe a metaxu or a migma theory to Anaximander, they were whistling in the dark. Anaximander’s text gave them no light; and I guess that they did not know what Anaximander thought, for the excellent reason that Anaximander himself did not know what to think. Argument (C) assumes, in (8), the spatial infinity of the universe. That proposition is the conclusion of argument (B). The argument is invalid, as Aristotle points out: In order that coming to be should not fail, it is not necessary that there should be a sensible body which is actually unlimited. The passing away of one thing may be the coming to be of another, the whole being limited’ (Phys 208a7–10). This objection is overcome by adding a further premiss to (B), viz: (18) The material supplied by the destruction of existing things cannot be used in the generation of new things. But it is implausible to ascribe (18) to Anaximander. Sentence [iv] of the fragment, whether or not it is Anaximandrian, is not, strictly speaking, incompatible with (18): [iv] does not imply that the dust produced by destroying a thing is equal in mass to the dust consumed in its generation; and it is not grossly implausible to imagine that the processes of generation and destruction involve a certain wastage of stuff. Sentence [v], however, suggests fairly strongly that Anaximander had some sort of equal balancing in mind; and the probability is that he would have rejected (18). Argument (B) can be repaired without the help of (18); instead of (18) we may add: (19) The mass of existing things is perpetually increasing. An adherent of (19) believes that the cosmos is expanding; and there is no direct evidence that any Presocratic held such a belief. But there is a sentence from Anaxagoras which apparently commits him to an expanding universe; and in some respects at least Anaxagoras was a scientific traditionalist. If Anaxagoras embraced (19), perhaps he took it from Anaximander. It is pertinent to quote here a fragment of Anaximander’s pupil, Anaximenes: Air is close to the incorporeal; and since we come into being by an effluxion of this, it is necessary for it to be both unlimited and rich, because it never gives out (18:13 B 3). The presocratic philosophers 26

[1]  J. Philip Parmenides' Theory of Knowledge , 1958 .

[2]  W. A. Heidel Qualitative Change in Pre-Socratic Philosophy. , 1906 .

[3]  A. Festugière Les « Mémoires pythagoriques » cités par Alexandre Polyhistor , 1945 .

[4]  L. Woodbury Parmenides on Names , 1958 .

[5]  J. Skemp,et al.  The Theory of Motion in Plato's Later Dialogues , 1942 .

[6]  R. Mathewson Aristotle and Anaxagoras: An Examination of F. M. Cornford's Interpretation , 1958, The Classical Quarterly.

[7]  D. Furley Empedocles and the Clepsydra , 1957, The Journal of Hellenic Studies.

[8]  F. M. Cornford Parmenides' Two Ways , 1933, The Classical Quarterly.

[9]  R. S. Bluck Plato, Pindar, and Metempsychosis , 1958 .

[10]  J. Mcdiarmid Theophrastus on the Presocratic Causes , 1953 .

[11]  Joseph P. Mueller Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology , 1961 .

[12]  G. Vlastos Ethics and Physics in Democritus , 1945 .

[13]  C. Bowra The Proem of Parmenides , 1937, Classical Philology.

[14]  Otto Regenbogen Eine Forschungsmethode antiker Naturwissenschaft , 1930 .

[15]  Adolfo Levi On "Twofold Statements." , 1940 .

[16]  B. Snell Die Nachrichten über die Lehren des Thales und die Anfänge der griechischen Philosophie- und Literaturgeschichte , 1944 .

[17]  W. A. Heidel Hecataeus and Xenophanes , 1943 .

[18]  C. Mugler AIcméon et les cycles physiologiques de Platon , 1958 .

[19]  E. Derenne Les Procès d'Impiété Intentés aux Philosophes À Athènes au Vme Et au Ivme Siècles Avant J.-C , 2022 .

[20]  F. M. Cornford Mysticism and Science in the Pythagorean Tradition , 1922, The Classical Quarterly.

[21]  G. Vlastos Theology and Philosophy in Early Greek Thought , 1952 .

[22]  F. Jacoby Some Remarks on Ion of Chios , 1947, The Classical Quarterly.

[23]  Gorgias and the Socratic Principle Nemo Sua Sponte Peccat , 1957 .

[24]  H. Frankel Zeno of Elea's Attacks on Plurality , 1942 .

[25]  O. Skutsch Notes on Metempsychosis , 1959, Classical Philology.

[26]  Florian Cajori The History of Zeno's Arguments on Motion , 1915 .

[27]  John Robinson Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility , 1953 .

[28]  N. Booth Empedocles' Account of Breathing , 1960, The Journal of Hellenic Studies.

[29]  A. Blumenthal,et al.  Ion von Chios. Die Reste seiner Werke , 1940 .

[30]  J. A. Davison Protagoras, Democritus, and Anaxagoras , 1953, The Classical Quarterly.

[31]  J. Morrison Parmenides and Er , 1955, The Journal of Hellenic Studies.

[32]  L. Stella,et al.  Importanza di Alcmeone nella storia del pensiero greco , 1942 .

[33]  C. Kahn RELIGION AND NATURAL PHILOSOPHY IN EMPEDOCLES’ DOCTRINE OF THE SOUL , 1960 .

[34]  G. SILYN ROBERTS,et al.  Achilles and the Tortoise , 1944, Nature.

[35]  G. Vlastos Equality and Justice in Early Greek Cosmologies , 1947, Classical Philology.

[36]  H. Frankel Heraclitus on God and the Phenomenal World , 1938 .

[37]  H. S. Long,et al.  A study of the doctrine of metempsychosis in Greece from Pythagoras to Plato , 1950 .

[38]  G. Owen Zeno and the Mathematicians , 1958 .

[39]  A. L. Peck Anaxagoras and the Parts , 1926, Classical Quarterly.

[40]  G. Kerferd Gorgias on nature or that which is not , 1955 .

[41]  G. Vlastos ON THE PRE-HISTORY IN DIODORUS , 2022, Studies in Greek Philosophy, Volume I.

[42]  Jellliffe THEOPHRASTUS AND THE GREEK PHYSIOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY BEFORE ARISTOTLE , 1921 .

[43]  G. Jameson "Well-rounded truth" and circular thought in Parmenides , 1958 .

[44]  L. E. C. H. This Physical World , 1942, Nature.

[45]  J. S. Morrison,et al.  Pythagoras of Samos , 1956, The Classical Quarterly.

[46]  B. Snell Die Ausdrücke für den Begriff des Wissens in der vorplatonischen Philosophie , 1924 .