Warp effects on calculating interval probabilities

In real-life decision analysis, the probabilities and utilities of consequences are in general vague and imprecise. One way to model imprecise probabilities is to represent a probability with the interval between the lowest possible and the highest possible probability, respectively. However, there are disadvantages with this approach; one being that when an event has several possible outcomes, the distributions of belief in the different probabilities are heavily concentrated toward their centres of mass, meaning that much of the information of the original intervals are lost. Representing an imprecise probability with the distribution's centre of mass therefore in practice gives much the same result as using an interval, but a single number instead of an interval is computationally easier and avoids problems such as overlapping intervals. We demonstrate why second-order calculations add information when handling imprecise representations, as is the case of decision trees or probabilistic networks. We suggest a measure of belief density for such intervals. We also discuss properties applicable to general distributions. The results herein apply also to approaches which do not explicitly deal with second-order distributions, instead using only first-order concepts such as upper and lower bounds.

[1]  P. J. Huber,et al.  Minimax Tests and the Neyman-Pearson Lemma for Capacities , 1973 .

[2]  Love Ekenberg,et al.  Value differences using second-order distributions , 2005, Int. J. Approx. Reason..

[3]  Love Ekenberg,et al.  Distribution of expected utility in decision trees , 2007, Int. J. Approx. Reason..

[4]  Matthias C. M. Troffaes Decision making under uncertainty using imprecise probabilities , 2007, Int. J. Approx. Reason..

[5]  Peter Walley,et al.  Towards a unified theory of imprecise probability , 2000, Int. J. Approx. Reason..

[6]  G. Choquet Theory of capacities , 1954 .

[7]  Glenn Shafer,et al.  A Mathematical Theory of Evidence , 2020, A Mathematical Theory of Evidence.

[8]  Arthur P. Dempster,et al.  Upper and Lower Probabilities Induced by a Multivalued Mapping , 1967, Classic Works of the Dempster-Shafer Theory of Belief Functions.

[9]  Patrick Suppes,et al.  Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science , 1963 .

[10]  Irving John Good,et al.  Subjective Probability as the Measure of a Non-measurable Set , 1962 .

[11]  Marek J. Druzdzel,et al.  Elicitation of Probabilities for Belief Networks: Combining Qualitative and Quantitative Information , 1995, UAI.

[12]  P. Walley Statistical Reasoning with Imprecise Probabilities , 1990 .

[13]  Love Ekenberg,et al.  Second-Order Decision Analysis , 2001, Int. J. Uncertain. Fuzziness Knowl. Based Syst..

[14]  D. Denneberg Non-additive measure and integral , 1994 .

[15]  AnHai Doan,et al.  Geometric foundations for interval-based probabilities , 1998, Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence.

[16]  Love Ekenberg,et al.  A framework for analysing decisions under risk , 1998 .