Belief representation in a deductivist type-free doxastic logic

Konolige's technical notion of belief based on deduction structures is briefly reviewed and its usefulness for the design of artificial agents with limited representational and deductive capacities is pointed out. The design of artificial agents with more sophisticated representational and deductive capacities is then taken into account. Extended representational capacities require in the first place a solution to the intensional context problems. As an alternative to Konolige's modal first-order language, an approach based on type-free property theory is proposed. It considers often neglected issues, such as the need for a more general account of thede dicto-de re distinction, and quasi-indicators. Extended deductive capacities require a subdivision of Konolige's notion of belief into two distinct technical notions,potential anddispositional belief. The former has to do with what an artificial agent could in principle come to actively believe, given enough time and its specific logical competence; the latter with what an agent can be assumed to believe with respect to a specific goal to be fulfilled.

[1]  Andrew R. Haas,et al.  Sentential Semantics for Propositional Attitudes , 1990, Comput. Linguistics.

[2]  G. Bealer Quality and concept , 1982 .

[3]  H. Castañeda Thinking and the structure of the world , 1974 .

[4]  K. Konolige A deduction model of belief , 1986 .

[5]  Nino B. Cocchiarella,et al.  Meinong reconstructed versus early russell reconstructed , 1982, J. Philos. Log..

[6]  Ronald Fagin,et al.  Belief, Awareness, and Limited Reasoning. , 1987, Artif. Intell..

[7]  Alonzo Church,et al.  A Formulation of the Logic of Sense and Denotation , 1952 .

[8]  H. Castañeda ON THE PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF THE THEORY OF COMMUNICATION: REFERENCE1 , 1977 .

[9]  Stuart C. Shapiro,et al.  SNePS Considered as a Fully Intensional Propositional Semantic Network , 1986, AAAI.

[10]  David J. Israel,et al.  Structured Meanings: The Semantics of Propositional Attitudes. , 1987 .

[11]  Hector-Neri Castañeda,et al.  On Philosophical Method. , 1980 .

[12]  J. Hintikka Knowledge and belief , 1962 .

[13]  William G. Lycan The Trouble with Possible Worlds , 1994 .

[14]  John A. Barnden,et al.  Imputations and Explications: Representational Problems in Treatments of Propositional Attitudes , 1986, Cogn. Sci..

[15]  Nino B. Cocchiarella,et al.  Frege, Russell and Logicism: A Logical Reconstruction , 1986 .

[16]  Richmond H. Thomason,et al.  A note on syntactical treatments of modality , 1980, Synthese.

[17]  H. Castañeda The Semantics and the Causal Roles of Proper Names , 1985 .

[18]  Ray Turner,et al.  A theory of properties , 1987, Journal of Symbolic Logic.

[19]  P. Strawson III.—ON REFERRING , 1950 .

[20]  B. Russell II.—On Denoting , 1905 .

[21]  Hector-Neri Castañeda,et al.  Thinking and Doing , 1975 .

[22]  Hans G. Herzberger,et al.  Notes on naive semantics , 1982, J. Philos. Log..

[23]  Richard Montague,et al.  The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English , 1973 .

[24]  Hector-Neri Castañeda Objects, Existence, and Reference A Prolegomenon to Guise Theory , 1985 .

[25]  John A. Barnden Imputations and Explications: Representational Problems in Treatments of Propositional Attitudes , 1986, Cogn. Sci..

[26]  The Theory of Questions, Epistemic Powers, and the Indexical Theory of Knowledge , 1980 .

[27]  William James,et al.  The Meaning of Truth , 1909 .

[28]  Jerry R. Hobbs Ontological Promiscuity , 1985, ACL.

[29]  P. French,et al.  Contemporary perspectives in the philosophy of language , 1989 .

[30]  Michael Jubien Problems with Possible Worlds , 1988 .

[31]  Lawrence H. Powers Knowledge by Deduction , 1978 .

[32]  Hector-Neri Castañeda I. The Semantics and the Causal Roles of Proper Names in our Thinking of Particulars: The Restricted-Variable/Retrieval View of Proper Names , 1990 .

[33]  H. Castañeda Perception, belief, and the structure of physical objects and consciousness , 1977, Synthese.

[34]  Barbara H. Partee,et al.  Montague Grammar, Mental Representations, and Reality , 1980 .

[35]  Hector J. Levesque,et al.  A Logic of Implicit and Explicit Belief , 1984, AAAI.

[36]  William J. Rapaport,et al.  Logical Foundations for Belief Representation , 1986 .

[37]  Carl Hewitt,et al.  Description and Theoretical Analysis (Using Schemata) of Planner: A Language for Proving Theorems and Manipulating Models in a Robot , 1972 .

[38]  Raymond Turner,et al.  Semantics and property theory , 1988 .

[39]  Francesco Orilia,et al.  Type-Free Property Theory, Exemplification and Russell's Paradox , 1991, Notre Dame J. Formal Log..

[40]  Saul A. Kripke,et al.  Naming and Necessity , 1980 .

[41]  Steven E. Boër,et al.  Knowing Who , 1985 .

[42]  N. Belnap,et al.  The Revision Theory of Truth , 1993 .

[43]  Hector-Neri Castañeda Reference, Reality and Perceptual Fields , 1980 .

[44]  N. Cocchiarella Conceptualism, realism, and intensional logic , 1989 .

[45]  Robert F. Hadley The many uses of ‘belief’ in AI , 1991, Minds and Machines.

[46]  Robert F. Hadley A sense-based, process model of belief , 1991, Minds and Machines.

[47]  William J. Rapaport,et al.  Logical Foundations for Belief Representation , 1986, Cogn. Sci..

[48]  Hector-Neri Castañeda,et al.  Thinking and Doing: The Philosophical Foundations of Institutions , 1975 .

[49]  Christopher Menzel A complete, type-free "second-order" logic and its philosophical foundations , 1986 .