The intentional mind and the hot hand: Perceiving intentions makes streaks seem likely to continue

People can appear inconsistent in their intuitions about sequences of repeated events. Sometimes people believe such sequences will continue (the "hot hand"), and sometimes people believe they will reverse (the "gambler's fallacy"). These contradictory intuitions can be partly explained by considering the perceived intentionality of the agent generating the streak. The intuition that streaks will continue (reverse) should emerge in contexts involving agents that are perceived to be intentional (unintentional), and should be most common among those who are most inclined to attribute intentions to other agents. Four studies support these predictions, identifying both situational and dispositional determinants of the perceived continuity of streaks. Discussion focuses on the foundational nature of intentionality for perceptions of interdependence between events, the relationship between these findings and existing theoretical accounts, and the inverse possibility that people use perceptions of streakiness as a cue for an agent's intentionality.

[1]  Robin R. Vallacher,et al.  Levels of personal agency: Individual variation in action identification. , 1989 .

[2]  J. Cacioppo,et al.  On seeing human: a three-factor theory of anthropomorphism. , 2007, Psychological review.

[3]  Student BELIEF IN THE LAW OF SMALL NUMBERS , 1994 .

[4]  A. Tversky,et al.  Judgment under Uncertainty , 1982 .

[5]  Peter Ayton,et al.  The hot hand fallacy and the gambler’s fallacy: Two faces of subjective randomness? , 2004, Memory & cognition.

[6]  J. J. Guajardo,et al.  Is agency skin-deep? Surface attributes influence infants' sensitivity to goal-directed action , 2004 .

[7]  Adam D. Galinsky,et al.  Lacking Control Increases Illusory Pattern Perception , 2008, Science.

[8]  Bruce D Burns,et al.  Randomness and inductions from streaks: “Gambler’s fallacy” versus ”hot hand“ , 2004, Psychonomic bulletin & review.

[9]  A. Tversky,et al.  Subjective Probability: A Judgment of Representativeness , 1972 .

[10]  A. Tversky,et al.  Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases , 1974, Science.

[11]  A. Woodward Infants selectively encode the goal object of an actor's reach , 1998, Cognition.

[12]  E. Langer,et al.  Heads I win, tails it's chance: The illusion of control as a function of the sequence of outcomes in a purely chance task. , 1975 .

[13]  Dare A. Baldwin,et al.  Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition , 2001 .

[14]  An T. Oskarsson,et al.  What’s Next? Judging Sequences of Binary Events , 2008, Psychological bulletin.

[15]  Carey K. Morewedge,et al.  Timescale bias in the attribution of mind. , 2007, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[16]  Evelyn Rosset It’s no accident: Our bias for intentional explanations , 2008, Cognition.

[17]  R. Dacey,et al.  Perception of randomness and predicting uncertain events , 2008 .

[18]  A. Tversky,et al.  The hot hand in basketball: On the misperception of random sequences , 1985, Cognitive Psychology.

[19]  Frank A. Schmid,et al.  Gambler’s fallacy? , 2002 .

[20]  J. Cacioppo,et al.  Who Sees Human? , 2010, Perspectives on psychological science : a journal of the Association for Psychological Science.

[21]  Gerd Gigerenzer,et al.  Adaptive Thinking: Rationality in the Real World , 2000 .

[22]  D. Dennett The Intentional Stance. , 1987 .

[23]  J. N. Bassili Temporal and spatial contingencies in the perception of social events , 1976 .

[24]  B. Malle,et al.  How People Explain Behavior: A New Theoretical Framework , 1999, Personality and social psychology review : an official journal of the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Inc.

[25]  M. Morris,et al.  Metaphors and the market: Consequences and preconditions of agent and object metaphors in stock market commentary , 2007 .

[26]  B. Malle,et al.  The Folk Concept of Intentionality , 1997 .

[27]  R. Shepherd It's no accident. , 2004, CMAJ : Canadian Medical Association journal = journal de l'Association medicale canadienne.

[28]  Eden Leone The Perfect Thing: How the iPod Shuffles Commerce, Culture, and Coolness , 2007 .

[29]  Robin R. Vallacher,et al.  A Theory Of Action Identification , 1985 .

[30]  John E. Opfer,et al.  Identifying living and sentient kinds from dynamic information: the case of goal-directed versus aimless autonomous movement in conceptual change , 2002, Cognition.

[31]  L. Buck,et al.  Encountering People Labeled "Schizophrenic" , 1997 .