Preference Aggregation After Harsanyi

Introduction Consider a group of people whose preferences satisfy the axioms of one of the current versions of utility theory, such as von Neumann–Morgenstern (1944), Savage (1954), or Bolker (1965)and Jeffrey (1965). There are political and economic contexts in which it is of interest to find ways of aggregating these individual preferences into a group preference ranking. The question then arises of whether methods of aggregation exist in which the group's preferences also satisfy the axioms of the chosen utility theory, while at the same time the aggregation process satisfies certain plausible conditions (e.g., the Pareto conditions introduced later). The answer to this question is sensitive to details of the chosen utility theory and method of aggregation. Much depends on whether uncertainty, expressed in terms of probabilities, is present in the framework and, if so, on how the probabilities are aggregated. The goal of this chapter is (a) to provide a conceptual map of the field of preference aggregation – with special emphasis, prompted by the occasion, on Harsanyi's aggregation result and its relations to other results – and (b) to present a new problem (“flipping”), which leads to a new impossibility result. The story begins with some bad news, roughly fifty years old, about “purely ordinal” frameworks, in which probabilities play no role. Arrow's General Possibility Theorem (1950, 1951, 1963) : No universally applicable nondictatorial method of aggregating individual preferences into group preferences can satisfy both the Pareto Preference condition (unanimous individual preferences are group preferences) and the condition of Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (group preference between two prospects depends only on individual preferences between those same prospects) .

[1]  John A. Weymark,et al.  Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-being: A reconsideration of the Harsanyi–Sen debate on utilitarianism , 1991 .

[2]  J. Harsanyi Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility , 1955 .

[3]  Ethan D. Bolker,et al.  A Simultaneous Axiomatization of Utility and Subjective Probability , 1967, Philosophy of Science.

[4]  R. Carnap,et al.  On Inductive Logic , 1945, Philosophy of Science.

[5]  A. Sen,et al.  Collective Choice and Social Welfare , 2017 .

[6]  R. Jeffrey Probability and the Art of Judgment , 1992 .

[7]  Joseph B. Kadane,et al.  You have printed the following article : On the Shared Preferences of Two Bayesian Decision Makers , 2008 .

[8]  P. Mongin Consistent Bayesian Aggregation , 1995 .

[9]  James M. Joyce The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory , 1999 .

[10]  P. Nicole,et al.  La logique, ou, L'art de penser , 1993 .

[11]  李幼升,et al.  Ph , 1989 .

[12]  D. F. Kerridge,et al.  The Logic of Decision , 1967 .

[13]  K. Arrow A Difficulty in the Concept of Social Welfare , 1950, Journal of Political Economy.

[14]  F. Ramsey The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays , 2001 .

[15]  L. A. Goodman,et al.  Social Choice and Individual Values , 1951 .

[16]  Isaac Levi,et al.  The Covenant Of Reason , 1997 .

[17]  Richard J. Zeckhauser,et al.  The Impossibility of Bayesian Group Decision Making with Separate Aggregation of Beliefs and Values , 1979 .

[18]  H. Jeffreys Logical Foundations of Probability , 1952, Nature.

[19]  E. Rowland Theory of Games and Economic Behavior , 1946, Nature.

[20]  D. G. Rees,et al.  Foundations of Statistics , 1989 .

[21]  Ethan D. Bolker,et al.  Functions resembling quotients of measures , 1966 .

[22]  Interpersonal Utility Comparisons , 1990 .

[23]  Abram Burk A Reformulation of Certain Aspects of Welfare Economics , 1938 .

[24]  John Broome Bolker-Jeffrey Expected Utility Theory and Axiomatic Utilitarianism , 1990 .

[25]  Kenneth J. Arrow,et al.  Readings in Welfare Economics , 1969 .

[26]  J. Marschak Rational Behavior, Uncertain Prospects, and Measurable Utility (1950) , 1950 .