Telling More Than We Can Know About Intentional Action

Recently, a number of philosophers have advanced a surprising conclusion: people's judgments about whether an agent brought about an outcome intentionally are pervasively influenced by normative considerations. In this paper, we investigate the 'Chairman case', an influential case from this literature and disagree with this conclusion. Using a statistical method called structural path modeling, we show that people's attributions of intentional action to an agent are driven not by normative assessments, but rather by attributions of underlying values and characterological dispositions to the agent. In a second study, we examined people's judgments about what they think drives asymmetric intuitions in the Chairman case and found that people are highly inaccurate in identifying which features of the case their intuitions track. In the final part of the paper, we discuss how the statistical methods used in this study can help philosophers with the critical features problem, the problem of figuring out which among the myriad features present in hypothetical cases are the critical ones that our intuitions are responsive to. We show how the methods used in this study have some advantages over both armchair methods used by traditional philosophers and survey methods used by experimental philosophers.

[1]  P. Bentler,et al.  Cutoff criteria for fit indexes in covariance structure analysis : Conventional criteria versus new alternatives , 1999 .

[2]  J. Ryan On Living High and Letting Die , 2000 .

[3]  Joshua Knobe,et al.  The Concept of Intentional Action: A Case Study in the Uses of Folk Psychology , 2006 .

[4]  Timothy D. Wilson,et al.  Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. , 1977 .

[5]  J R Nesselroade,et al.  Reporting structural equation modeling results in Psychology and Aging: some proposed guidelines. , 1991, Psychology and aging.

[6]  Chandra Sekhar Sripada,et al.  The Deep Self Model and asymmetries in folk judgments about intentional action , 2010 .

[7]  Thomas Nadelhoffer On Praise, Side Effects, and Folk Ascriptions of Intentionality. , 2004 .

[8]  Timothy Williamson,et al.  The Philosophy of Philosophy , 2022 .

[9]  J. Knobe,et al.  Variantism about Responsibility , 2007, Character Trouble.

[10]  P. Shrout,et al.  Mediation in experimental and nonexperimental studies: new procedures and recommendations. , 2002, Psychological methods.

[11]  J. Uleman,et al.  Spontaneous inferences, implicit impressions, and implicit theories. , 2008, Annual review of psychology.

[12]  Peter M. Bentler,et al.  EQS : structural equations program manual , 1989 .

[13]  M. Alicke Culpable Causation , 2004 .

[14]  B. Latané,et al.  The Unresponsive Bystander: Why Doesn't He Help? , 1972 .

[15]  Jennifer Cole Wright,et al.  Asymmetries in Judgments of Responsibility and Intentional Action , 2009 .

[16]  Joshua Knobe,et al.  The Pervasive Impact of Moral Judgment , 2009 .

[17]  Ron Mallon,et al.  Intention, Temporal Order, and Moral Judgments , 2008 .

[18]  The Folk Concept of Intentional Action: A Commentary , 2006 .

[19]  Thomas Nadelhoffer Bad acts, blameworthy agents, and intentional actions: Some problems for juror impartiality , 2006 .

[20]  Thomas Nadelhoffer Blame, Badness, and Intentional Action: A Reply to Knobe and Mendlow. , 2004 .

[21]  J. Knobe Intentional Action and Side Effects in Ordinary Language , 2003 .

[22]  R. Holton Norms and the Knobe effect , 2010 .

[23]  Wesley Buckwalter,et al.  The Epistemic Side-Effect Effect , 2010 .

[24]  Edmund L. Gettier Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? , 1963, Arguing About Knowledge.

[25]  Joshua Knobe,et al.  Theory of mind and moral cognition: exploring the connections , 2005, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[26]  D. A. Kenny,et al.  The moderator-mediator variable distinction in social psychological research: conceptual, strategic, and statistical considerations. , 1986, Journal of personality and social psychology.