Stable Causal Relationships are Better Causal Relationships

We report three experiments investigating whether people's judgments about causal relationships are sensitive to the robustness or stability of such relationships across a range of background circumstances. In Experiment 1, we demonstrate that people are more willing to endorse causal and explanatory claims based on stable (as opposed to unstable) relationships, even when the overall causal strength of the relationship is held constant. In Experiment 2, we show that this effect is not driven by a causal generalization's actual scope of application. In Experiment 3, we offer evidence that stable causal relationships may be seen as better guides to action. Collectively, these experiments document a previously underappreciated factor that shapes people's causal reasoning: the stability of the causal relationship.

[1]  L. Allan A note on measurement of contingency between two binary variables in judgment tasks , 1980 .

[2]  Noah D. Goodman,et al.  A pragmatic theory of generic language , 2016, ArXiv.

[3]  S. Carey,et al.  Functional explanation and the function of explanation , 2006, Cognition.

[4]  E. Markman,et al.  The generic/nongeneric distinction influences how children interpret new information about social others. , 2011, Child development.

[5]  P. Cheng From covariation to causation: A causal power theory. , 1997 .

[6]  J. Tenenbaum,et al.  Structure and strength in causal induction , 2005, Cognitive Psychology.

[7]  Alex Shaw,et al.  Manipulating Morality: Third-Party Intentions Alter Moral Judgments by Changing Causal Reasoning , 2015, Cogn. Sci..

[8]  P. Johnson-Laird,et al.  Causal reasoning with mental models , 2014, Front. Hum. Neurosci..

[9]  Philip N. Johnson-Laird,et al.  Naive causality: a mental model theory of causal meaning and reasoning1 , 2001, Cogn. Sci..

[10]  Sandeep Prasada,et al.  Principled and statistical connections in common sense conception , 2006, Cognition.

[11]  Sarah-Jane Leslie,et al.  Conceptual distinctions amongst generics , 2013, Cognition.

[12]  Mimi Liljeholm,et al.  When is a cause the "same"? Coherent generalization across contexts. , 2007, Psychological science.

[13]  Phillip Wolff,et al.  Causal reasoning with forces , 2015, Front. Hum. Neurosci..

[14]  James F. Woodward The problem of variable choice , 2015, Synthese.

[15]  James Woodward,et al.  Causation in biology: stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation , 2010 .

[16]  Sandeep Prasada,et al.  Representation of Principled Connections: A Window Onto the Formal Aspect of Common Sense Conception , 2009, Cogn. Sci..

[17]  F. J. Pelletier Kinds, Things, and Stuff , 2009 .

[18]  J. Woodward Sensitive and Insensitive Causation , 2006 .

[19]  T. Lombrozo Causal–explanatory pluralism: How intentions, functions, and mechanisms influence causal ascriptions , 2010, Cognitive Psychology.

[20]  Noah D. Goodman,et al.  Communicating generalizations about events , 2016, CogSci.

[21]  Joshua B. Tenenbaum,et al.  How, whether, why: Causal judgments as counterfactual contrasts , 2015, CogSci.

[22]  Simon Stephan,et al.  Mediators or alternative explanations: Transitivity in human-mediated causal chains , 2015 .

[23]  P. White,et al.  Causal judgement: use of different types of contingency information as confirmatory and disconfirmatory , 1998 .

[24]  P. Cheng,et al.  Assessing interactive causal influence. , 2004, Psychological review.

[25]  Joshua Knobe,et al.  Causality, Normality, and Sampling Propensity , 2016, CogSci.

[26]  Susan Goldin-Meadow,et al.  Expressing generic concepts with and without a language model , 2005, Cognition.

[27]  T. Lombrozo,et al.  Stability, breadth and guidance , 2018 .

[28]  Samuel G. B. Johnson,et al.  Causal Networks or Causal Islands? The Representation of Mechanisms and the Transitivity of Causal Judgment , 2015, Cogn. Sci..

[29]  Kenneth S Kendler,et al.  "A gene for...": the nature of gene action in psychiatric disorders. , 2006, The American journal of psychiatry.

[30]  J. Knobe,et al.  Cause and Norm , 2009 .

[31]  S. Sloman,et al.  Causal invariance in reasoning and learning , 2003 .

[32]  Barbara A. Spellman,et al.  Acting as Intuitive Scientists: Contingency Judgments Are Made While Controlling for Alternative Potential Causes , 1996 .

[33]  Jon R. Star,et al.  Children's Use of Generics in Inductive Inferences , 2002 .

[34]  Robert A. Wilson Causality in the Mind: Estimating Contextual and Conjunctive Causal Power , 2006 .

[35]  S. Leslie Carving Up the Social World with Generics , 2014 .

[36]  Jonas Nagel,et al.  Explanations in Causal Chains: Selecting Distal Causes Requires Exportable Mechanisms , 2016 .

[37]  A. Cohen Generics, Frequency Adverbs, and Probability , 1999 .

[38]  S. Sloman Causal Models: How People Think about the World and Its Alternatives , 2005 .

[39]  Tania Lombrozo,et al.  Effects of Manipulation on Attributions of Causation, Free Will, and Moral Responsibility , 2017, Cogn. Sci..

[40]  K. Holyoak,et al.  Causal competition based on generic priors , 2016, Cognitive Psychology.

[41]  Joshua B. Tenenbaum,et al.  Noisy Newtons: Unifying process and dependency accounts of causal attribution , 2012, CogSci.

[42]  Patricia W. Cheng,et al.  Logical Consistency and Objectivity in Causal Learning , 2013, CogSci.

[43]  Steven A. Sloman,et al.  A Causal Model Theory of the Meaning of Cause, Enable, and Prevent , 2009, Cogn. Sci..