Does the Stock Market Rationally Reflect Fundamental Values

This paper examines the power of statistical tests commonly used to evaluate the efficiency of speculative markets. It shows that these tests have very low power. Market valuations can differ substantially and persistently from the rational expectation of the present value of cash flows without leaving statistically discernible traces in the pattern of ex-post returns. This observation implies that speculation is unlikely to ensure rational valuations, since similar problems of identification plague both financial economists and would be speculators. THE PROPOSITION THAT securities markets are efficient forms the basis for most research in financial economics. A voluminous literature has developed supporting this hypothesis. Jensen [10] calls it the best established empirical fact in economics.1 Indeed, apparent anomalies such as the discounts on closed end mutual funds and the success of trading rules based on earnings announcements are treated as indications of the failures of models specifying equilibrium returns, rather than as evidence against the hypothesis of market efficiency.2 Recently the Efficient Markets Hypothesis and the notions connected with it have provided the basis for a great deal of research in macroeconomics. This research has typically assumed that asset prices are in some sense rationally related to economic realities. Despite the widespread allegiance to the notion of market efficiency, a number of authors have suggested that certain asset prices are not rationally related to economic realities. Modigliani and Cohn [14] suggest that the stock market is very substantially undervalued because of inflation illusion. A similar claim regarding bond prices is put forward in Summers [20]. Brainard, Shoven and Weiss [4] find that the currently low level of the stock market could not be rationally related to economic realities. Shiller [16, 17] concludes that both bond and stock prices are far more volatile than can be justified on the basis of real economic events. Arrow [2] has suggested that psychological models of "irrational decision making" of the type suggested by Tversky and Kahneman [22] can help to explain behavior in speculative markets. These types of claims are frequently

[1]  J. Shoven,et al.  The Financial Valuation of the Return to Capital , 1980 .

[2]  Dennis E. Logue,et al.  Foundations of Finance. , 1977 .

[3]  M. Watson,et al.  Bubbles, Rational Expectations and Financial Markets , 1982 .

[4]  R. Shiller,et al.  The Use of Volatility Measures in Assessing Market Efficiency , 1980 .

[5]  M. Resnik,et al.  Aspects of Scientific Explanation. , 1966 .

[6]  Frederic S. Mishkin,et al.  An Integrated View of Tests of Rationality, Market Efficiency, and the Short-Run Neutrality of Monetary Policy , 1981 .

[7]  Roger G. Ibbotson,et al.  Stocks, Bonds, Bills, and Inflation: Year-by-Year Historical Returns (1926-1974) , 1976 .

[8]  K. Arrow Risk Perception in Psychology and Economics , 1982 .

[9]  F. Modigliani,et al.  INFLATION, RATIONAL VALUATION, AND THE MARKET , 1979 .

[10]  V. Roley,et al.  Rational Expectations, the Expectations Hypothesis, and Treasury Bill Yields: An Econometric Analysis , 1982 .

[11]  R. Shiller The Volatility of Long-Term Interest Rates and Expectations Models of the Term Structure , 1979, Journal of Political Economy.

[12]  J. Keynes,et al.  The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money. , 1936 .

[13]  S. Schaefer,et al.  Tax-induced clientele effects in the market for British government securities : Placing bounds on security values in an incomplete market , 1982 .

[14]  Robert C. Merton,et al.  On the current state of the stock market rationality hypothesis , 1985 .

[15]  A. Tversky,et al.  The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. , 1981, Science.

[16]  C. Granger,et al.  Forecasting Economic Time Series. , 1988 .