The strategy of model-based science

My title refers to Richard Levins’ famous paper on models in population biology (1966). Here Levins presented his three-way distinction between kinds of modelbuilding, and also introduced a set of more fundamental ideas about trade-offs that constrain and guide scientific work. For Levins, these trade-offs derive from the relationships between three different theoretical goals: realism, precision, and generality. The talk of ‘‘strategies’’ within Levins’ paper concerns alternative strategies within the enterprise of model-building. My topic here is broader; I will treat models and model-building as characteristic of one particular approach to theorizing, a strategy of model-based science. The ideas presented here are indebted to Michael Weisberg’s work (forthcoming, 2003), and to discussions with him at Stanford. They are also indebted to a scattered tradition of other philosophical and scientific work, especially by Levins, Giere, and Wimsatt. The aim of the paper is to give a general sketch of model-based science as I see it, but a sketch focusing particularly on divergences between myself and those on whose work I draw. The term ‘‘model’’ is surely one of the most contested in all of philosophy of science. What sense of the term do I have in mind? My starting point is the account given by Giere (1988). For Giere, models are idealized structures that we use to

[1]  D. Queller Cooperators Since Life Began , 1997, The Quarterly Review of Biology.

[2]  R. Giere The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science , 2003 .

[3]  Eörs Szathmáry,et al.  The Major Transitions in Evolution , 1997 .

[4]  R. Michod Darwinian Dynamics: Evolutionary Transitions in Fitness and Individuality , 1999 .

[5]  Models, Mathematics and Metaphors , 1963 .

[6]  Lorenzo Magnani,et al.  Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery , 1999, Springer US.

[7]  The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory , 1990 .

[8]  Peter Godfrey-Smith,et al.  Complexity and the function of mind in nature: Foundations , 1996 .

[9]  T. Kuhn,et al.  The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. , 1964 .

[10]  Patrick Suppes A comparison of the meaning and uses of models in mathematics and the empirical sciences , 1960 .

[11]  R. Levins THEORY OF FITNESS IN A HETEROGENEOUS ENVIRONMENT. 3. THE RESPONSE TO SELECTION. , 1964, Journal of theoretical biology.

[12]  P. Godfrey‐Smith Complexity and the function of mind in nature , 1996 .

[13]  Peter Godfrey-Smith,et al.  The Dimensions of Selection , 1993, Philosophy of Science.

[14]  Anjan Chakravartty,et al.  The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science , 2000 .

[15]  F. Suppe The Structure of Scientific Theories. , 1975 .

[16]  Nancy J. Nersessian,et al.  Model-Based Reasoning in Conceptual Change , 1999 .

[17]  Martin Thomson-Jones,et al.  Models and the Semantic View , 2006, Philosophy of Science.

[18]  P. Johnson-Laird,et al.  Mental Models: Towards a Cognitive Science of Language, Inference, and Consciousness , 1985 .

[19]  R. Lewontin Models, mathematics and metaphors , 2004, Synthese.

[20]  N. Cartwright The dappled world : a study of the boundaries of science , 1999 .

[21]  Stephen M. Downes,et al.  The Importance of Models in Theorizing: A Deflationary Semantic View , 1992, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

[22]  Margaret Morrison,et al.  Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science , 1999 .

[23]  George C. Williams,et al.  The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory , 1990 .

[24]  Michael Weisberg Who is a Modeler? , 2007, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

[25]  R. Levins Evolution in Changing Environments , 1968 .

[26]  James Ladyman,et al.  Reinflating the Semantic Approach , 1999 .

[27]  Richard T. Hull,et al.  The Structure and Confirmation of Evolutionary Theory. , 1988 .

[28]  R. Levins Theory of Fitness in a Heterogeneous Environment. I. The Fitness Set and Adaptive Function , 1962, The American Naturalist.

[29]  Bas C. van Fraassen,et al.  The Scientific Image , 1980 .

[30]  Ronald N. Giere,et al.  Using Models to Represent Reality , 1999 .

[31]  James R. Griesemer,et al.  Material Models in Biology , 1990, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

[32]  R. Klatzky,et al.  Mental Models, Psychology of , 1991 .

[33]  R. Levins The strategy of model building in population biology , 1966 .

[34]  D. Lewis,et al.  Putnam's paradox , 1984 .

[35]  R. Giere Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach , 1991 .

[36]  L. Buss,et al.  The evolution of individuality , 1987 .

[37]  D. Krantz The structure of scientific theories. 2nd ed. , 1978 .

[38]  A. Hoffman,et al.  Neutral models in biology , 1987 .

[39]  P. Suppes A comparison of the meaning and uses of models in mathematics and the empirical sciences , 1960, Synthese.

[40]  R. Levins Theory of Fitness in a Heterogeneous Environment. II. Developmental Flexibility and Niche Selection , 1963, The American Naturalist.

[41]  T. Kuhn The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 2nd edition , 1970 .