When representations conflict with reality: The preschooler's problem with false beliefs and “false” photographs

It has been argued that young preschoolers cannot correctly attribute a false belief to a deceived actor (Wimmer & Perner, 1983). Some researchers claim that the problem lies in the child's inadequate epistemology (Chandler & Boyes, 1982; Wellman, 1988); as such, it is specific to the child's theory of mind and no such problem should appear in reasoning about nonmental representations. This prediction is tested below in the "false photograph" task: here an actor takes a photograph of an object in location X; the object is then moved to location Y. Preschool subjects are asked: "In the picture, where is the object?" Results indicate that photographs are no easier to reason about than are beliefs. Manipulations to boost performance on the photograph task proved ineffective. Further, an explanation of the failure as a processing limitation having nothing to do with the representational nature of beliefs or photographs was ruled out. It is argued that young children's failure on the false belief task is not due to an inadequate epistemology (though they may have one) and is symptomatic of a larger problem with representations.

[1]  S. Baron-Cohen,et al.  Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind” ? , 1985, Cognition.

[2]  H. Wellman,et al.  Children's understanding of mental phenomena. , 1989, Advances in child development and behavior.

[3]  Michael Siegal,et al.  Misleading children: Causal attributions for inconsistency under repeated questioning ☆ , 1988 .

[4]  C N Johnson,et al.  Children's developing conceptions of the mind and brain. , 1982, Child development.

[5]  H. Wimmer,et al.  Three-year-olds' difficulty with false belief: The case for a conceptual deficit , 1987 .

[6]  H. Beilin,et al.  Children's belief in photographic fidelity. , 1981 .

[7]  J. Block,et al.  Longitudinally foretelling drug usage in adolescence: early childhood personality and environmental precursors. , 1988, Child development.

[8]  B. H. Pillow The Development of Children's Beliefs about the Mental World. , 1988 .

[9]  H. E. Howe,et al.  Social cognitive development , 1978 .

[10]  H. Wimmer,et al.  Ignorance versus false belief: a developmental lag in attribution of epistemic states , 1986 .

[11]  H. Wellman,et al.  Early understanding of mental entities: a reexamination of childhood realism. , 1986, Child development.

[12]  H. Wimmer,et al.  “John thinks that Mary thinks that…” attribution of second-order beliefs by 5- to 10-year-old children ☆ , 1985 .

[13]  M. Maratsos,et al.  Early comprehension of mental verbs: Think and know , 1977 .

[14]  Josef Perner,et al.  Children's Understanding of Informational Access as Source of Knowledge. , 1988 .

[15]  H. Wimmer,et al.  Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children's understanding of deception , 1983, Cognition.

[16]  John H. Flavell,et al.  The development of children's knowledge about the mind: From cognitive connections to mental representations. , 1988 .

[17]  A. Leslie Pretense and representation: The origins of "theory of mind." , 1987 .

[18]  A. Leslie Some implications of pretense for mechanisms underlying the child's theory of mind. , 1988 .

[19]  J. Fodor Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind , 1988 .

[20]  M. Blank,et al.  The potency of context in children's cognition: An illustration through conservation. , 1974 .

[21]  D. Premack,et al.  Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? , 1978, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.