PAYOFF DOMINANCE AND THE STACKELBERG HEURISTIC

Payoff dominance, a criterion for choosing between equilibrium points in games, is intuitively compelling, especially in matching games and other games of common interests, but it has not been justified from standard game-theoretic rationality assumptions. A psychological explanation of it is offered in terms of a form of reasoning that we call the Stackelberg heuristic in which players assume that their strategic thinking will be anticipated by their co-player(s). Two-person games are called Stackelberg-soluble if the players' strategies that maximize against their co-players' best replies intersect in a Nash equilibrium. Proofs are given that every game of common interests is Stackelberg-soluble, that a Stackelberg solution is always a payoff-dominant outcome, and that in every game with multiple Nash equilibria a Stackelberg solution is a payoff-dominant equilibrium point. It is argued that the Stackelberg heuristic may be justified by evidentialist reasoning.

[1]  R. Sugden Thinking as a Team: Towards an Explanation of Nonselfish Behavior , 1993, Social Philosophy and Policy.

[2]  V. Crawford,et al.  Learning How to Cooperate: Optimal Play in Repeated Coordination Games , 1990 .

[3]  T. Schelling The Strategy of Conflict , 1963 .

[4]  H. Stackelberg,et al.  Marktform und Gleichgewicht , 1935 .

[5]  John C. Turner,et al.  Stereotyping and Social Reality , 1994 .

[6]  A. Tversky,et al.  The simulation heuristic , 1982 .

[7]  M. Hewstone Causal Attribution: From Cognitive Processes to Collective Beliefs , 1989 .

[8]  J. Neumann,et al.  Theory of games and economic behavior , 1945, 100 Years of Math Milestones.

[9]  Shelley E. Taylor,et al.  Social cognition, 2nd ed. , 1991 .

[10]  R. Sugden Rational Choice: A Survey of Contributions from Economics and Philosophy , 1991 .

[11]  Diane M. Mackie,et al.  Affect, cognition, and stereotyping: Interactive processes in group perception. , 1993 .

[12]  M. Bacharach,et al.  An Experimental Study of the Variable Frame Theory of Focal Points , 1995 .

[13]  D. Lutz,et al.  Paradoxes of Rationality: Theory of Metagames and Political Behavior , 1973 .

[14]  David Lewis Convention: A Philosophical Study , 1986 .

[15]  R. Sugden,et al.  Focal points in pure coordination games: An experimental investigation , 1994 .

[16]  John C. Harsanyi,et al.  Общая теория выбора равновесия в играх / A General Theory of Equilibrium Selection in Games , 1989 .

[17]  William Harper,et al.  Counterfactuals and Two Kinds of Expected Utility , 1978 .

[18]  L. Anderlini,et al.  Communication, Computability And Common Interest Games , 1999 .

[19]  Joseph Farrell Communication, coordination and Nash equilibrium , 1988 .

[20]  Michael Bacharach,et al.  A theory of rational decision in games , 1987 .

[21]  R. Sugden A Theory of Focal Points , 1995 .

[22]  Amos Tversky,et al.  Causal versus diagnostic contingencies: On self-deception and on the voter's illusion. , 1984 .

[23]  N. Howard The present and future of metagame analysis , 1987 .

[24]  D. Stahl,et al.  Experimental evidence on players' models of other players , 1994 .

[25]  A. Colman Game Theory and its Applications: In the Social and Biological Sciences , 1995 .

[26]  Dov Samet,et al.  Unanimity games and Pareto optimality , 1985 .

[27]  Robert Nozick,et al.  Newcomb’s Problem and Two Principles of Choice , 1969 .

[28]  ‘General’ Metagames: An Extension of the Metagame Concept , 1974 .

[29]  R. Aumann,et al.  Cooperation and bounded recall , 1989 .