1. Introduction. Two opposing tendencies in the philosophy of language go by the names of 'referentialism' and 'inferentialism' respectively. In the crudest version of the contrast, the referentialist account of meaning gives centre stage to the referential semantics for a language, which is then used to explain the inference rules for the language, perhaps as those which preserve truth on that semantics (since a referential semantics for a language determines the truth-conditions of its sentences). By contrast, the inferentialist account of meaning gives centre stage to the inference rules for the language, which are then used to explain its referential semantics, perhaps as the semantics on which the rules preserve truth. On pain of circularity, we cannot combine both directions of explanation. Of course, this simple opposition may not survive more refined definitions of 'referentialism' and 'inferentialism'. Not all of those willing to apply one or other term to their views would accept the crude characterizations just given. Nevertheless, the two styles of theorizing often function as rivals in practice. There is a corresponding contrast in the philosophy of thought, concerning the reference of concepts, rather than of 1 expressions of a public language, and inferential connections between thoughts, rather than between sentences. 2 3 If inferentialists appealed only to inference rules, they could not hope to explain how many words refer to extra-linguistic objects, or how language is used in interaction with the extra-linguistic environment. We may therefore assume that, in addition to intra-linguistic rules such as the introduction and elimination rules for the logical constants in a Gentzen-style system of natural deduction, inferentialists may also advert to 'language-entry' rules that connect perceptual states to moves in the language game, and 'language-exit' rules that connect moves in the language game to non-linguistic actions. Inferential roles are thereby generalized as conceptual roles. 1 The details do not matter here, for the overall picture is the same. The rules by which speakers use the language have explanatory primacy. The referential semantics is a kind of epiphenomenon. At least on the simplest versions of inferentialism, understanding a word is equated with using it according to the appropriate rules, not with having propositional knowledge of its referential meaning: practice is prior to theory. At first sight, inferentialism may appear to be a conservative or quietist view: since whatever rules the speech community uses thereby determine a semantics on which those very rules come …
[1]
Arthur N. Prior,et al.
The Runabout Inference-Ticket
,
1960
.
[2]
Laurence R. Horn.
A Natural History of Negation
,
1989
.
[3]
Nuel D. Belnap,et al.
Tonk, Plonk and Plink
,
1962
.
[4]
P. Boghossian.
How Are Objective Epistemic Reasons Possible?
,
2001
.
[5]
Roy Sorensen,et al.
Vagueness and Contradiction
,
2001
.
[6]
I. Rumfitt,et al.
Yes and no
,
2000
.
[7]
David Kaplan.
Demonstratives: An Essay on the Semantics, Logic, Metaphysics and Epistemology of Demonstratives and other Indexicals
,
1989
.
[8]
R. Carston.
Thoughts and Utterances
,
2002
.
[9]
Robert Kirk,et al.
A Study of Concepts
,
1994
.
[10]
Steven E. Boër,et al.
Knowing Who
,
1985
.
[11]
P. Boghossian.
The Rule-Following Considerations1
,
1989
.
[12]
Robyn Carston,et al.
Thoughts and Utterances: The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication
,
2002
.
[13]
R. Brandom,et al.
Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism
,
2002
.
[14]
Keith DeRose.
Knowledge and its Limits
,
2002
.
[15]
Jennifer Hornsby.
Meaning and Uselessness: How to Think about Derogatory Words
,
2001
.
[16]
Michael Dummett,et al.
The logical basis of metaphysics
,
1991
.
[17]
Stephen Barker.
Truth and Conventional Implicature
,
2003
.
[18]
Robert Stalnaker.
Context And Content
,
1999
.
[19]
Saul A. Kripke,et al.
A Puzzle about Belief
,
1979
.
[20]
I. Levi,et al.
Making It Explicit
,
1994
.
[21]
Gottlob Frege,et al.
Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens
,
1879
.
[22]
K. Bach.
The Myth of Conventional Implicature
,
1999
.
[23]
Timothy Williamson,et al.
VII—Equivocation and Existence
,
1988
.
[24]
A. Avramides.
Studies in the Way of Words
,
1992
.
[25]
M. Bradie,et al.
The Causal Theory of Perception
,
1976,
Synthese.
[26]
Christopher Peacocke,et al.
Implicit Conceptions, Understanding and Rationality
,
1998
.
[27]
I. Rumfitt,et al.
Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment.
,
1997
.
[28]
M. Dummett.
Frege: Philosophy of Language
,
1973
.
[29]
Michael Dummett,et al.
Wang's paradox
,
1975,
Synthese.
[30]
David Kaplan.
Quantifying in
,
2004,
Synthese.
[31]
K. Bach.
Varieties of Reference
,
1994
.