ON THE UTILITY THEORETIC FOUNDATIONS OF MEAN‐VARIANCE ANALYSIS

THE CHOICE MODEL in which alternatives are ordered in terms of the mean and variance of their return has been utilized in a variety of fields with the best developed, both theoretically and empirically, being that of portfolio selection. Since the pioneering works of Markowitz [22] and Tobin [32], a series of results has been obtained regarding the utility theoretic foundations of this model. While these results are widely known, they continue to be the source of discussion.' For example, Markowitz demonstrated that if the ordering of alternatives is to satisfy the von Neumann-Morgenstern (NM) [35] axioms of rational behavior, only a quadratic (NM) utility function is consistent with an ordinal expected utility function that depends solely on the mean and variance of the return. Consequently, even if the return for each alternative has a normal distribution, the mean-variance framework cannot be used to rank alternatives consistently with the NM axioms unless a quadratic NM utility function is specified. The implications of this restriction are disturbing not only because of the undesirable properties of a quadratic utility function but also because, for example, the indifference curves in the mean-standard deviation plane are concentric circles with the center on the mean axis. Furthermore, a quadratic utility function leads to a rather disquieting result in portfolio theory, since it implies that in equilibrium each investor holds an equal percentage of every security (Mossin [23, p. 69]). Also, Ekern and Wilson [11, p. 179] have shown that in a mean-variance portfolio model all shareholders prefer that a firm characterized by stochastic constant returns operate so that its market value is zero. Another disquieting result is that of Borch [7] who demonstrates that if preferences satisfy a monotonicity condition, an indifference curve in the ( ,a)-plane consists of a single point. A number of authors, including Samuelson [27] [29] and Tsiang [33], have argued that mean-variance analysis may be viewed as an approximation to a more general choice model. The appropriateness of such an approximation has been considered by Borch [8], Bierwag [6], Levy [20], and Tsiang [34], for example, and will not be considered further here. The purpose of this paper is instead to consider the foundations of mean-variance analysis and the consistency of the ordering of alternatives according to means and variances with the NM axioms. More specifically, given alternatives a, and a2 and their corresponding random returns X, and X2 with distribution functions F,(x) and F2(x), respectively, preferences satisfying the NM axioms imply the existence of a measurable, continuous utility function

[1]  J. Neumann,et al.  Theory of games and economic behavior , 1945, 100 Years of Math Milestones.

[2]  P. Samuelson The Fundamental Approximation Theorem of Portfolio Analysis in terms of Means, Variances and Higher Moments , 1970 .

[3]  G. O. Bierwag The Rationale of the Mean-Standard Deviation Analysis: Comment , 1974 .

[4]  E. Fama Portfolio Analysis in a Stable Paretian Market , 1965 .

[5]  Karl Borch,et al.  The Rationale of the Mean-Standard Deviation Analysis: Comment , 1974 .

[6]  W. Sharpe CAPITAL ASSET PRICES: A THEORY OF MARKET EQUILIBRIUM UNDER CONDITIONS OF RISK* , 1964 .

[7]  S. Turnovsky,et al.  Safety-First and Expected Utility Maximization in Mean-Standard Deviation Portfolio Analysis , 1970 .

[8]  Mukhtar M. Ali Stochastic dominance and portfolio analysis , 1975 .

[9]  M. Allais Le comportement de l'homme rationnel devant le risque : critique des postulats et axiomes de l'ecole americaine , 1953 .

[10]  Paul Anthony Samuelson,et al.  Efficient Portfolio Selection for Pareto-Lévy Investments , 1967, Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis.

[11]  A. Klevorick A Note on "The Ordering of Portfolios in Terms of Mean and Variance" , 1973 .

[12]  J. Tobin Liquidity Preference as Behavior towards Risk , 1958 .

[13]  J. Lintner,et al.  The Market Price of Risk, Size of Market and Investor's Risk Aversion , 1970 .

[14]  M. Feldstein,et al.  Mean-Variance Analysis in the Theory of Liquidity Preference and Portfolio Selection , 1969 .

[15]  V. Bawa OPTIMAL, RULES FOR ORDERING UNCERTAIN PROSPECTS+ , 1975 .

[16]  K. Borch,et al.  A Note on Uncertainty and Indifference Curves , 1969 .

[17]  S. Tsiang The Rationale of the Mean-Standard Deviation Analysis, Skewness Preference, and the Demand for Money , 1972 .

[18]  S. Kataoka A Stochastic Programming Model , 1963 .

[19]  Jan Mossin Theory of financial markets , 1972 .

[20]  Haim Levy,et al.  Stochastic Dominance among Log-Normal Prospects , 1973 .

[21]  Haim Levy,et al.  Efficient Portfolio Selection with Quadratic and Cubic Utility , 1970 .

[22]  P. Samuelson General Proof that Diversification Pays , 1967, Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis.

[23]  Peter C. Fishburn,et al.  Convex stochastic dominance with continuous distribution functions , 1974 .

[24]  Robert B. Wilson,et al.  On the theory of the firm in an economy with incomplete markets , 1974 .

[25]  M. A. Grove,et al.  Indifference Curves in Asset Analysis , 1966 .

[26]  Joseph E. Stiglitz,et al.  On the Optimality of the Stock Market Allocation of Investment , 1972 .

[27]  H. Levy,et al.  Efficiency analysis of choices involving risk , 1969 .

[28]  S. Tsiang,et al.  The Rationale of the Mean-Standard Deviation Analysis: Reply and Errata for Original Article , 1972 .

[29]  Haim Levy,et al.  The Rationale of the Mean-Standard Deviation Analysis: Comment , 1974 .

[30]  John S. Chipman,et al.  The Ordering of Portfolios in Terms of Mean and Variance , 1973 .

[31]  M. Allais L'Extension des Theories de l'Equilibre Economique General et du Rendement Social au Cas du Risque , 1953 .

[32]  A. Roy Safety first and the holding of assetts , 1952 .