A theory of individual-level predicates based on blind mandatory scalar implicatures

Predicates such as tall or to know Latin, which intuitively denote permanent properties, are called individual-level predicates. Many peculiar properties of this class of predicates have been noted in the literature. One such property is that we cannot say #John is sometimes tall. Here is a way to account for this property: this sentence sounds odd because it triggers the scalar implicature that the alternative John is always tall is false, which cannot be, given that, if John is sometimes tall, then he always is. This intuition faces two challenges. First: this scalar implicature has a weird nature, since it must be surprisingly robust (otherwise, it could be cancelled and the sentence rescued) and furthermore blind to the common knowledge that tallness is a permanent property (since this piece of common knowledge makes the two alternatives equivalent). Second: it is not clear how this intuition could be extended to other, more complicated properties of individual-level predicates. The goal of this paper is to defend the idea of an implicature-based theory of individual-level predicates by facing these two challenges. In the first part of the paper, I try to make sense of the weird nature of these special mismatching implicatures within the recent grammatical framework for scalar implicatures of Chierchia (Structures and beyond, 2004) and Fox (2007). In the second part of the paper, I show how this implicature-based line of reasoning can be extended to more complicated properties of individual-level predicates, such as restrictions on the interpretation of their bare plural subjects, noted in Carlson (Reference to kinds in English. Doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst, 1977), Milsark (Linguistic Analysis 3.1: 1–29, 1977), and Fox (Natural Language Semantics 3: 283–341, 1995); restrictions on German word order, noted in Diesing (Indefinites, 1992); and restrictions on Q-adverbs, noted in Kratzer (The Generic Book, ed. Carlson and Pelletier, 125–175, 1995).

[1]  Jeffrey Gruber Studies in lexical relations , 1965 .

[2]  Laurence R. Horn,et al.  On the semantic properties of logical operators in english' reproduced by the indiana university lin , 1972 .

[3]  H. Grice Logic and conversation , 1975 .

[4]  Gregory Norman Carlson,et al.  Reference to kinds in English , 1977 .

[5]  Gerald Gazdar,et al.  Pragmatics: Implicature, Presupposition, and Logical Form , 1978 .

[6]  David R. Dowty,et al.  Word Meaning and Montague Grammar , 1979 .

[7]  Janet Dean Fodor,et al.  The linguistic description of opaque contexts , 1979 .

[8]  Irene Heim,et al.  The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases : a dissertation , 1982 .

[9]  Mats Rooth Association with focus , 1985 .

[10]  An empty category as the subject of a tensed S in English , 1986 .

[11]  Lenhart K. Schubert,et al.  Generically Speaking, or, Using Discourse Representation Theory to Interpret Generics , 1989 .

[12]  J. Hawkins On (in)definite articles: implicatures and (un)grammaticality prediction , 1991, Journal of Linguistics.

[13]  D. Fox Economy and scope , 1995 .

[14]  Renate Irene Musan,et al.  On the Temporal Interpretation of Noun Phrases , 2021 .

[15]  Angelika Kratzer,et al.  Stage-Level and Individual-Level Predicates , 1995 .

[16]  Renate Musan,et al.  Tense, Predicates, and Lifetime Effects , 1997 .

[17]  Sheila Glasbey I-Level Predicates that Allow Existential Readings for Bare Plurals , 1997 .

[18]  Kai von Fintel,et al.  Bare Plurals, Bare Conditionals, and Only , 1997, J. Semant..

[19]  Katalin É. Kiss,et al.  On Generic and Existential Bare Plurals and the Classification of Predicates , 1998 .

[20]  L. McNally Stativity and Theticity , 1998 .

[21]  G. Chierchia,et al.  Reference to Kinds across Language , 1998 .

[22]  Danny Fox,et al.  Economy and Semantic Interpretation , 1999 .

[23]  Fred Landman,et al.  Events And Plurality , 2000 .

[24]  Claudia Maienborn,et al.  On the Position and Interpretation of Locative Modifiers , 2001 .

[25]  Gerhard Jäger,et al.  Topic‐Comment Structure and the Contrast Between Stage Level and Individual Level Predicates , 2001, J. Semant..

[26]  Nomi Erteschik-Shir,et al.  Topic, Focus, and the Interpretation of Bare Plurals , 2002 .

[27]  Uli Sauerland,et al.  Scalar Implicatures in Complex Sentences , 2004 .

[28]  J. Gajewski Neg-raising : polarity and presupposition , 2005 .

[29]  Marcelo Ferreira Event quantification and plurality , 2005 .

[30]  Danny Fox,et al.  The universal density of measurement , 2007 .

[31]  Robert van Rooij,et al.  Pragmatic Meaning and Non-monotonic Reasoning: The Case of Exhaustive Interpretation , 2006 .

[32]  Benjamin Spector Aspects de la pragmatique des opérateurs logiques , 2006 .

[33]  Benjamin Russell,et al.  Against Grammatical Computation of Scalar Implicatures , 2006, J. Semant..

[34]  G. Chierchia,et al.  Broaden Your Views: Implicatures of Domain Widening and the Logicality of Language , 2006, Linguistic Inquiry.

[35]  D. Fox Free Choice and the Theory of Scalar Implicatures , 2007 .

[36]  Benjamin Spector Aspects of the Pragmatics of Plural Morphology: On Higher-Order Implicatures , 2007 .

[37]  Benjamin Spector 10: Scalar Implicatures: Exhaustivity and Gricean Reasoning , 2007 .

[38]  Barbara H. Partee,et al.  Toward the Logic of Tense and Aspect in English , 2008 .

[39]  H. Kamp A Theory of Truth and Semantic Representation , 2008 .

[40]  Bart Geurts,et al.  Scalar implicature and local pragmatics. , 2009 .