Why Heideggerian AI Failed and How Fixing it Would Require Making it More Heideggerian

When I was teaching at MIT in the 1960s, students from the Artificial Intelligence Laboratory would come to my Heidegger course and say in effect: ‘‘You philosophers have been reflecting in your armchairs for over 2000 years and you still don’t understand intelligence. We in the AI Lab have taken over and are succeeding where you philosophers have failed.’’ But in 1963, when I was invited to evaluate the work of Alan Newell and Herbert Simon on physical symbol systems, I found to my surprise that, far from replacing philosophy, these pioneering researchers had learned a lot, directly and indirectly, from us philosophers: e.g., Hobbes’ claim that reasoning was calculating, Descartes’ mental representations, Leibniz’s idea of a ‘universal characteristic’ (a set of primitives in which all knowledge could be expressed), Kant’s claim that concepts were rules, Frege’s formalization of such rules, and Wittgenstein’s postulation of logical atoms in his Tractatus. In short, without realizing it, AI researchers were hard at work turning rationalist philosophy into a research program. But I began to suspect that the insights formulated in existentialist armchairs, especially Heidegger’s and Merleau-Ponty’s, were bad news for those working in AI laboratories—that, by combining representationalism, conceptualism, formalism,

[1]  Sean D. Kelly Content and Constancy: phenomenology, psychology, and the content of perception , 2008 .

[2]  W. Freeman The place of 'codes' in nonlinear neurodynamics. , 2007, Progress in brain research.

[3]  R. Gaskin Experience and judgement , 2006 .

[4]  W. Freeman,et al.  Nonlinear brain dynamics as macroscopic manifestation of underlying many-body field dynamics , 2005, q-bio/0511037.

[5]  Béla Bollobás,et al.  Phase transitions in the neuropercolation model of neural populations with mixed local and non-local interactions , 2005, Biological Cybernetics.

[6]  M. Wheeler Reconstructing the Cognitive World: The Next Step , 2005 .

[7]  Taylor Carman,et al.  Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty , 2004 .

[8]  S. Dreyfus Totally Model-Free Learned Skillful Coping , 2004 .

[9]  Taylor Carman,et al.  The Cambridge Companion to Merleau-Ponty , 2004 .

[10]  Robert Kozma,et al.  Basic principles of the KIV model and its application to the navigation problem. , 2003, Journal of integrative neuroscience.

[11]  Péter Érdi,et al.  The KIV model - nonlinear spatio-temporal dynamics of the primordial vertebrate forebrain , 2003, Neurocomputing.

[12]  John D. Van Buren,et al.  Supplements: From the Earliest Essays to Being and Time and Beyond , 2002 .

[13]  M. Bishop,et al.  Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence , 2002 .

[14]  James L. Olds,et al.  How brains make up their mind , 2001, Complex..

[15]  S. Todes Body and world , 2001 .

[16]  H. Dreyfus,et al.  Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus , 2000 .

[17]  Edgar A. Whitley,et al.  The Construction of Social Reality , 1999 .

[18]  L. Baker Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind. , 1999 .

[19]  W. Freeman How Brains Make Up Their Minds , 1999 .

[20]  A. Clark,et al.  The Extended Mind , 1998, Analysis.

[21]  John Haugeland Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind , 1998 .

[22]  Rodney A. Brooks,et al.  From earwigs to humans , 1997, Robotics Auton. Syst..

[23]  W. Freeman Societies of Brains: A Study in the Neuroscience of Love and Hate. By W. J. Freeman. Erlbaum: Hillsdale, NJ. 1994. , 1997, Psychological Medicine.

[24]  J. Searle The Construction of Social Reality , 1997 .

[25]  Daniel C. Dennett,et al.  The practical requirements for making a conscious robot , 1994, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series A: Physical and Engineering Sciences.

[26]  Daniel C. Dennett,et al.  Consciousness in Human and Robot Minds , 1994 .

[27]  Hubert L. Dreyfus,et al.  What computers still can't do - a critique of artificial reason , 1992 .

[28]  W. Freeman The physiology of perception. , 1991, Scientific American.

[29]  R. A. Brooks,et al.  Intelligence without Representation , 1991, Artif. Intell..

[30]  Philip E. Agre,et al.  The dynamic structure of everyday life , 1988 .

[31]  Geoffrey Hunter What Computers Can't Do , 1988, Philosophy.

[32]  W J Freeman,et al.  Relation of olfactory EEG to behavior: factor analysis. , 1987, Behavioral neuroscience.

[33]  J. Fodor The Modularity of mind. An essay on faculty psychology , 1986 .

[34]  James L. McClelland,et al.  Phenomenology of perception. , 1978, Science.

[35]  Дрейфус Хьюберт,et al.  Чего не могут вычислительные машины: Критика искусственного разума. (What computers cant do: A critique of artificial reason) , 1978 .

[36]  Roger C. Schank,et al.  Scripts, plans, goals and understanding: an inquiry into human knowledge structures , 1978 .

[37]  M. Heidegger,et al.  Gesamtausgabe.@@@Band 21: Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit. , 1977 .

[38]  Peter Madsen Logik: Die Frage nach der Wahrheit , 1977 .

[39]  Allen Newell,et al.  Computer science as empirical inquiry: symbols and search , 1976, CACM.

[40]  Edmund Husserl,et al.  Experience and judgment , 1973 .

[41]  G. J. Whitrow Reflections on the history of the concept of time. , 1970, Studium generale; Zeitschrift fur die Einheit der Wissenschaften im Zusammenhang ihrer Begriffsbildungen und Forschungsmethoden.

[42]  T. Hirao [Structure of behavior]. , 1967, Nihon Ishikai zasshi. Journal of the Japan Medical Association.

[43]  Maurice Merleau-Ponty The structure of behavior , 1963 .

[44]  R. Hepburn,et al.  BEING AND TIME , 2010 .