Why people die in novels: testing the ordeal simulation hypothesis

What is fiction about, and what is it good for? An influential family of theories sees fiction as rooted in adaptive simulation mechanisms. In this view, our propensity to create and enjoy narrative fictions was selected and maintained due to the training that we get from mentally simulating situations relevant to our survival and reproduction. We put forward and test a precise version of this claim, the “ordeal simulation hypothesis”. It states that fictional narrative primarily simulates “ordeals”: situations where a person’s reaction might dramatically improve or decrease her fitness, such as deadly aggressions, or decisions on long-term matrimonial commitments. Experience does not prepare us well for these rare, high-stakes occasions, in contrast with situations that are just as fitness-relevant but more frequent (e.g., exposure to pathogens). We study mortality in fictional and non-fictional texts as a partial test for this view. Based on an analysis of 744 extensive summaries of twentieth century American novels of various genres, we show that the odds of dying (in a given year) are vastly exaggerated in fiction compared to reality, but specifically more exaggerated for homicides as compared to suicides, accidents, war-related, or natural deaths. This evidence supports the ordeal simulation hypothesis but is also compatible with other accounts. For a more specific test, we look for indications that this focus on death, and in particular on death caused by an agent, is specific to narrative fiction as distinct from other verbal productions. In a comparison of 10,810 private letters and personal diary entries written by American women, with a set of 811 novels (also written by American women), we measure the occurrence of words related to natural death or agentive death. Private letters and diaries are as likely, or more likely, to use words relating to natural or agentive death. Novels written for an adult audience contain more words relating to natural deaths than do letters (though not diary entries), but this is not true for agentive death. Violent death, in spite of its clear appeal for fiction, does not necessarily provide a clear demarcation point between fictional and non-fictional content.

[1]  Lucas M Bietti,et al.  Storytelling as Adaptive Collective Sensemaking , 2018, Top. Cogn. Sci..

[2]  Michelle Scalise Sugiyama Food, foragers, and folklore: the role of narrative in human subsistence , 2001 .

[3]  J. Bruner Life as Narrative , 2014 .

[4]  Lisa Zunshine,et al.  Why We Read Fiction: Theory of Mind and the Novel , 2006 .

[5]  K. Vohs,et al.  Case Western Reserve University , 1990 .

[6]  S. Pinker How the Mind Works , 1999, Philosophy after Darwin.

[7]  Donald E. Brown HUMAN UNIVERSALS , 2008, Science.

[8]  Peter C. Kjærgaard,et al.  Biocultural Theory: The Current State of Knowledge , 2017 .

[9]  K. M. Thompson,et al.  Violence in E-rated video games. , 2001, JAMA.

[10]  H. Barrett,et al.  Adaptations to Predators and Prey , 2015 .

[11]  J. Pennebaker,et al.  Psychological aspects of natural language. use: our words, our selves. , 2003, Annual review of psychology.

[12]  A. Revonsuo,et al.  Dreaming and consciousness: Testing the threat simulation theory of the function of dreaming. , 2000 .

[13]  Emanuele Castano,et al.  Reading Literary Fiction Improves Theory of Mind , 2013, Science.

[14]  Cindy K. Chung,et al.  The development and psychometric properties of LIWC2007 , 2007 .

[15]  D. Symons Social Behavior: A Quantitative Study. (Book Reviews: Play and Aggression. A Study of Rhesus Monkeys) , 1977 .

[16]  Ellen Dissanayake An Ethological View of Ritual and Art in Human Evolutionary History , 1979 .

[17]  P. Boyer,et al.  Origins of sinister rumors: A preference for threat-related material in the supply and demand of information , 2018 .

[18]  Joseph Carroll,et al.  Reading Human Nature: Literary Darwinism in Theory and Practice , 2011 .

[19]  J. Peskin Guise and Guile: Children's Understanding of Narratives in Which the Purpose of Pretense Is Deception , 1996 .

[20]  Daniel Nettle,et al.  The Wheel of Fire and the Mating Game: Explaining the Origins of Tragedy and Comedy , 2005 .

[21]  John A. Johnson,et al.  Horror, personality, and threat simulation: A survey on the psychology of scary media. , 2020 .

[22]  D. Fessler BELIEVING CHICKEN LITTLE: EVOLUTIONARY PERSPECTIVES ON CREDULITY AND DANGER , 2018, DRUMS.

[23]  Alex Mesoudi,et al.  A bias for social information in human cultural transmission. , 2006, British journal of psychology.

[24]  P. Boyer,et al.  Threat-Related Information Suggests Competence: A Possible Factor in the Spread of Rumors , 2015, PloS one.

[25]  Emma Flynn,et al.  Serial killers, spiders and cybersex: Social and survival information bias in the transmission of urban legends. , 2015, British journal of psychology.

[26]  P. Boyer,et al.  Why ritualized behavior? Precaution Systems and action parsing in developmental, pathological and cultural rituals , 2006, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[27]  Vladimir Propp,et al.  Morphology of the folktale , 1959 .

[28]  R. Nesse,et al.  The Smoke Detector Principle , 2001, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences.

[29]  W. Frankenhuis,et al.  Mapping the Cultural Learnability Landscape of Danger. , 2016, Child development.

[30]  Anne C. Pisor,et al.  Negatively-Biased Credulity and the Cultural Evolution of Beliefs , 2014, PloS one.

[31]  D. Sperber,et al.  Optimistic expectations about communication explain children's difficulties in hiding, lying, and mistrusting liars* , 2016, Journal of Child Language.

[32]  D. Fry Play aggression among zapotec children: Implications for the practice hypothesis , 1990 .

[33]  Keith Oatley,et al.  The Function of Fiction is the Abstraction and Simulation of Social Experience , 2008, Perspectives on psychological science : a journal of the Association for Psychological Science.

[34]  K.W.M. van Krieken,et al.  How reading narratives can improve our fitness to survive , 2018, Narrative Inquiry.

[35]  A. Revonsuo The reinterpretation of dreams: an evolutionary hypothesis of the function of dreaming. , 2000, The Behavioral and brain sciences.

[36]  A. Revonsuo,et al.  The reinterpretation of dreams: An evolutionary hypothesis of the function of dreaming , 2000, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[37]  John Tooby,et al.  Does Beauty Build Adapted Minds? Toward an Evolutionary Theory of Aesthetics, Fiction, and the Arts , 2001 .

[38]  T. M. Ellison,et al.  The sky is falling: evidence of a negativity bias in the social transmission of information , 2017 .

[39]  A. Zadra,et al.  Evolutionary function of dreams: A test of the threat simulation theory in recurrent dreams , 2006, Consciousness and Cognition.

[40]  Keith Oatley,et al.  Such Stuff as Dreams: The Psychology of Fiction , 2011 .

[41]  K M Thompson,et al.  Violence in G-rated animated films. , 2000, JAMA.

[42]  Katja Mellmann Is Storytelling a Biological Adaptation? Preliminary Thoughts on How to Pose That Question , 2012 .

[43]  D. Lancy Play in Species Adaptation , 1980 .

[44]  Anushka Ataullahjan,et al.  CARTOONS KILL: casualties in animated recreational theater in an objective observational new study of kids’ introduction to loss of life , 2014, BMJ : British Medical Journal.

[45]  Mary Beth Oliver,et al.  Portrayals of crime, race, and aggression in “reality‐based” police shows: A content analysis , 1994 .

[46]  N. Goodman,et al.  Ways of Worldmaking , 1980 .

[47]  Brian A. Nosek,et al.  Evaluating the replicability of social science experiments in Nature and Science between 2010 and 2015 , 2018, Nature Human Behaviour.

[48]  Olivier Morin,et al.  Birth of the cool: a two-centuries decline in emotional expression in Anglophone fiction , 2017, Cognition & emotion.

[49]  J. Piaget Play, dreams and imitation in childhood , 1951 .

[50]  B. Hill,et al.  Such stuff as dreams , 1967 .