A way is indicated to derive, from a preference relation on a Cartesian product, strength of preference relations on the coordinate sets. These strengths of preference relations are then used to reformulate several well-known properties of preference relations, and make their meaning more transparent. A new result for dynamic contexts is given. This paper examines the existence of several kinds of additively decomposable representing functions for preference relations on Cartesian products. This is done under the assumption that the coordinate sets are connected topological spaces, e.g., R y, or Iw. The representing functions which we shall find will be cardinal. Several authors have dealt with cardinal additively decomposable representing functions under the assumption that the coordinate sets are ‘mixture spaces’, the main intended examples of mixture spaces being sets of probability distributions. See, for instance, Anscombe and Aumann (1963), Fishburn (1965), Polk& (1967), Keeney and Raiffa (1976, Karni, Schmeidler and Vind (1983). Usually the axioms of von Neumann and Morgenstem (1953, ch. 3 and the appendix) are assumed, leading to linear representing functions. Cardinality is easily obtained in the presence of linearity because, if one linear function is a (strictly increasing) transformation of another linear function, then in fact it must be a linear transformation. Hence, if two linear functions induce the same preference relation, then they also induce the same strength of preference relation. Matters are more complicated if the assumption of linearity is weakened to the assumption of continuity. To see this, let f and g be two continuous functions on a connected domain. Let f = cp . g for a transformation cp. For guaranteeing that cp is (positively) linear, the assumption of strict increasingness of cp no longer suffices. It must be strengthened to the more complicated assumption that cp preserves (‘first-order’) differences, as shown in Basu (1982). The characterizing properties for preference relations on connected topological spaces, met in literature, reflect this additional complication. This paper handles the additional complication by indicating a way to derive, from a preference relation on a Cartesian product (‘revealed’), strength of preference relations on the coordinate sets. By means of these we formulate several properties and results, met in literature, for connected topological spaces. All reformulated versions will require that certain strengths of preferences,
[1]
Robert A. Pollak,et al.
Additive von Neumann-Morgenstern Utility Functions
,
1967
.
[2]
L. J. Savage,et al.
The Foundations of Statistics
,
1955
.
[3]
P. Wakker.
Continuous expected utility for arbitrary state spaces
,
1985
.
[4]
J. Neumann,et al.
Theory of games and economic behavior
,
1945,
100 Years of Math Milestones.
[5]
L. J. Savage,et al.
The Foundations of Statistics
,
1955
.
[6]
Peter C. Fishburn,et al.
Independence in Utility Theory with Whole Product Sets
,
1965
.
[7]
K. Basu.
Determinateness of the Utility Function: Revisiting a Controversy of the Thirties
,
1982
.
[8]
G. Debreu.
Topological Methods in Cardinal Utility Theory
,
1959
.
[9]
F. J. Anscombe,et al.
A Definition of Subjective Probability
,
1963
.
[10]
Aldo Montesano,et al.
Recent Developments in the Foundations of Utility and Risk Theory
,
1986
.
[11]
P. Wakker.
Concave Additively Decomposable Representing Functions and Risk Aversion
,
1986
.
[12]
Edi Karni,et al.
On State-Dependent Prefer-ences and Subjective Probabilities
,
1983
.
[13]
Jaap Van Brakel,et al.
Foundations of measurement
,
1983
.
[14]
T. Koopmans,et al.
Two papers on the representation of preference orderings : representation of preference orderings with independent components of consumption, and, Representation of preference orderings over time
,
1972
.
[15]
A. Tversky,et al.
Foundations of Measurement, Vol. I: Additive and Polynomial Representations
,
1991
.
[16]
Peter P. Wakker,et al.
Cardinal coordinate independence for expected utility
,
1984
.
[17]
P. Samuelson.
An Exact Consumption-Loan Model of Interest with or without the Social Contrivance of Money
,
1958,
Journal of Political Economy.
[18]
H. Bandemer.
Savage, L. J.: Foundations of Statistics. Dover Publ., Inc,. New York 1972. 310 S.
,
1974
.