Controlling core knowledge: conditions for the ascription of intentional states to self and others by children

The ascription of intentional states to the self involves knowledge, or at least claims to knowledge. Armed with the working definition of knowledge as ‘the ability to do things, or refrain from doing things, or believe, or want, or doubt things, for reasons that are facts’ [Hyman, J. Philos. Quart. 49:432–451], I sketch a simple competence model of acting and believing from knowledge and when knowledge is defeated by un-experienced changes of state. The model takes the form of three concentric circles. The ‘periphery’ is analogous to Fodor’s [(1983), The modularity of mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA] input systems. The ‘core’ contains copies of peripheral representations, and between these representations there is executive competition. At the ‘nucleus’, operations are performed on the core representations of, at least, negation and recursion. I argue that this provides a fruitful way in which to conceptualise why theory-of-mind tasks challenge pre-school children, how some degree of first-person authority is mental state attribution is possible, and how executive inhibition is achieved.

[1]  J. Perner,et al.  Development of theory of mind and executive control , 1999, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[2]  H. Wimmer,et al.  Three-year-olds' difficulty with false belief: The case for a conceptual deficit , 1987 .

[3]  P. Zelazo,et al.  An age-related dissociation between knowing rules and using them ☆ , 1996 .

[4]  P. Zelazo,et al.  Rule selection versus rule execution in preschoolers: an error-detection approach. , 1999, Developmental psychology.

[5]  Alison Gopnik,et al.  How we know our minds , 1993 .

[6]  J. Russell,et al.  The execution of arbitrary procedures by children with autism , 2001, Development and Psychopathology.

[7]  J. Fodor The Modularity of mind. An essay on faculty psychology , 1986 .

[8]  A. Woodward Infants selectively encode the goal object of an actor's reach , 1998, Cognition.

[9]  Catharine H. Echols,et al.  Infants' understanding of false labeling events: the referential roles of words and the speakers who use them , 2003, Cognition.

[10]  A. Gopnik,et al.  Why the Child's Theory of Mind Really Is a Theory , 1992 .

[11]  Donald M. Peterson,et al.  Are errors in false belief tasks symptomatic of a broader difficulty with counterfactuality , 1998 .

[12]  Jane Heal,et al.  Theories of theories of mind: Simulation, theory, and content , 1996 .

[13]  A. Leslie Pretense and representation: The origins of "theory of mind." , 1987 .

[14]  Noam Chomsky Language and thought , 1993 .

[15]  H. Wimmer,et al.  Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children's understanding of deception , 1983, Cognition.

[16]  Josef Perner,et al.  Children's Understanding of Informational Access as Source of Knowledge. , 1988 .

[17]  James A. Russell,et al.  The ‘windows task’ as a measure of strategic deception in preschoolers and autistic subjects , 1991 .

[18]  S. Carey,et al.  Whose gaze will infants follow? Features that elicit gaze-following in twelve-month-olds , 1996 .

[19]  James Russell What is language development? : rationalist, empiricist, and pragmatist approaches to the acquisition of syntax , 2004 .

[20]  José Luis Bermúdez The Paradox of Self-Consciousness , 1998 .

[21]  D. Povinelli,et al.  Young children's understanding of briefly versus extremely delayed images of the self: emergence of the autobiographical stance. , 1998, Developmental psychology.

[22]  A. Gopnik How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality , 1993, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[23]  M. Tomasello,et al.  Do chimpanzees know what conspecifics know? , 2001, Animal Behaviour.

[24]  A. Diamond Close interrelation of motor development and cognitive development and of the cerebellum and prefrontal cortex. , 2000, Child development.

[25]  D. Povinelli,et al.  Reasoning about beliefs: a human specialization? , 2001, Child development.

[26]  Donald A. Norman,et al.  Attention to Action , 1986 .

[27]  G. McCulloch,et al.  The Varieties of Reference. , 1984 .

[28]  E. Spelke,et al.  Origins of knowledge. , 1992, Psychological review.

[29]  John H. Flavell,et al.  Development of the appearance-reality distinction , 1983, Cognitive Psychology.

[30]  E. Spelke Nativism, empiricism, and the origins of knowledge , 1998 .

[31]  David R. Olson,et al.  Developing theories of intention : social understanding and self-control , 1999 .

[32]  M. Tomasello,et al.  A nonverbal false belief task: the performance of children and great apes. , 1999, Child development.

[33]  Noam Chomsky,et al.  The Minimalist Program , 1992 .

[34]  H. Wimmer,et al.  False Belief Understanding in Young Children: Explanations do not Develop Before Predictions , 1998 .

[35]  A. Lillard,et al.  Pretend play skills and the child's theory of mind. , 1993, Child development.

[36]  Z. Nadasdy,et al.  Taking the intentional stance at 12 months of age , 1995, Cognition.

[37]  D. Norman,et al.  Attention to action: Willed and automatic control , 1980 .

[38]  Nancy E. Reed,et al.  Practical Reasoning , 1996, Lecture Notes in Computer Science.

[39]  John Hyman,et al.  How Knowledge Works , 1999 .

[40]  J. Perner,et al.  ‘He Thinks He Knows’: And More Developmental Evidence Against the Simulation (Role Taking) Theory , 1992 .

[41]  Jane Heal,et al.  Mind, Reason and Imagination: Selected Essays in Philosophy of Mind and Language , 2003 .

[42]  M. Forrester Agency: Its role in mental development , 1999 .

[43]  R. Baillargeon A model of physical reasoning in infancy , 1995 .

[44]  H. Bekkering,et al.  Developmental psychology: Rational imitation in preverbal infants , 2002, Nature.

[45]  Alan M. Leslie,et al.  Belief-desire reasoning as a process of selection , 2005, Cognitive Psychology.

[46]  R. Baillargeon,et al.  Do 15-Month-Old Infants Understand False Beliefs? , 2005, Science.

[47]  K. Pribram,et al.  Error recognition and utilization produced by injury to the frontal cortex in man. , 1970, Neuropsychologia.

[48]  Alfred R. Mele,et al.  Springs Of Action , 1992 .

[49]  Josef Perner,et al.  Language and thought: The meta-intentional nature of executive functions and theory of mind , 1998 .

[50]  Jane Heal,et al.  ON FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY , 2001 .

[51]  S. Carey,et al.  Whose gaze will infants follow? The elicitation of gaze-following in 12-month-olds , 1998 .

[52]  J. Searle Intentionality: Name index , 1983 .

[53]  J. Russell,et al.  Action-monitoring and intention reporting in children with autism. , 2001, Journal of child psychology and psychiatry, and allied disciplines.

[54]  R. Davidson,et al.  Consciousness and Self-Regulation: Advances in Research and Theory IV , 1976 .

[55]  J. Burnheim Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics , 1959 .

[56]  Peter K. Smith,et al.  Theories of Theories of Mind , 1996 .

[57]  J. Bermúdez,et al.  The Paradox of Self-Consciousness , 1998 .

[58]  Christopher Peacocke,et al.  Our Entitlement to Self-Knowledge , 1995 .

[59]  M. Tomasello,et al.  Cooperation and human cognition: the Vygotskian intelligence hypothesis , 2007, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences.

[60]  Donald F. Gustafson On Unconscious Intentions , 1973 .

[61]  Josef Perner,et al.  Executive functions and theory of mind: Cognitive complexity or functional dependence? , 1999 .

[62]  P. Harris The work of imagination , 1991 .

[63]  Crispin Wright,et al.  Wittgenstein 's Later Philosophy of Mind: Sensation, Privacy, and Intention , 1989 .

[64]  D. Povinelli,et al.  Self-recognition in young children using delayed versus live feedback: evidence of a developmental asynchrony. , 1996, Child development.

[65]  D. Davidson Essays on actions and events , 1980 .

[66]  Hilary Kornblith,et al.  Perception, learning, and the self , 1983 .

[67]  M. Chandler,et al.  Small-scale deceit: deception as a marker of two-, three-, and four-year-olds' early theories of mind. , 1989, Child development.

[68]  James A. Russell,et al.  Autistic children's difficulty with mental disengagement from an object: Its implications for theories of autism. , 1993 .

[69]  A. Goldman,et al.  Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading , 1998, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[70]  J. Perner Understanding the Representational Mind , 1993 .

[71]  Peter F. Strawson,et al.  Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics , 1979 .

[72]  D. Povinelli,et al.  Development of young children's understanding that the recent past is causally bound to the present. , 1999, Developmental psychology.

[73]  H. Wellman,et al.  Scaling of theory-of-mind tasks. , 2004, Child development.

[74]  T. Ruffman,et al.  Why do infants make A not B errors in a search task, yet show memory for the location of hidden objects in a nonsearch task? , 1998, Developmental psychology.

[75]  H Wimmer,et al.  Misinformation and unexpected change: Testing the development of epistemic-state attribution , 1988, Psychological research.

[76]  Edmund L. Gettier Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? , 1963, Arguing About Knowledge.