2 Why the distinction between basic ( theoretical ) and applied ( practical ) research is important in the politics of science

The term “basic research” is ubiquitous in present debates on policy in science and higher education. It is a term with positive connotations, important for example in legitimising traditional universities. The popular term “researc h” generally corresponds to “research and development” (R&D) in official statistics. This inc ludes “applied research” and “technological development” as well as “basic resea rch.” In public discourse these distinctions are regularly overlooked. “Research” s imply includes” the whole of R&D. The public neglect of the differences corresponds to a trend in science studies. Within present historical, philosophical, sociological, economic, etc. studies of science and technology there is a strong tendency to play down the difference be twe n applied and basic research, or between science and technology, or explicitly to re ject it as relevant to the politics or governance of science. This paper argues that more respect for these differences would improve the chances of developing a politics of sci en e to serve society as a whole and not only the special interests of certain groups, be th ey private enterprises, political movements, particular religions, the scientific community, or others. Introduction This paper aims to recover and demonstrate the pres nt relevance of an understanding of basic science that was still widely taken for granted hal f a century ago. It was then often called “pure science” or simply “science.” On this view tr uthfulness is the root value and scientific research is perceived as a search for truth that ou ght to be as free as possible from the

[1]  A. Elzinga,et al.  The university research system : the public policies of the home of scientists , 1987 .

[2]  I. Niiniluoto The aim and structure of applied research , 1993 .

[3]  Robert K. Merton,et al.  Science and the Social Order , 1938, Nature.

[4]  H. Longino The Fate of Knowledge , 2001 .

[5]  H. Longino Science and the Common Good: Thoughts on Philip Kitcher’s Science, Truth, and Democracy , 2002, Philosophy of Science.

[6]  S. Schwartzman,et al.  The New Production of Knowledge: The Dynamics of Science and Research in Contemporary Societies , 1994 .

[7]  Nikolai Krementsov,et al.  :The Lysenko Effect: The Politics of Science , 2006 .

[8]  F. Dagognet Méthodes et doctrine dans l'œuvre de Pasteur ... , 1967 .

[9]  J. Ravetz Sociology of Science , 1972, Nature.

[10]  P. David,et al.  Toward a new economics of science , 1994 .

[11]  Steve Fuller,et al.  Kuhn vs. Popper: The Struggle for the Soul of Science , 2003 .

[12]  Criteria for Scientific Development: Public Policy and National Goals , 1968 .

[13]  Philip Mirowski,et al.  Science Bought and Sold: Essays in the Economics of Science , 2002 .

[14]  J. Wilson Science, Truth, and Democracy , 2002 .

[15]  Bør OECD-målsettingen i norsk forskningspolitikk opprettholdes? , 2004 .

[16]  R. Nelson The Simple Economics of Basic Scientific Research , 1959, Journal of Political Economy.

[17]  E. Brody Science as Social Knowledge. Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry , 1990 .

[18]  Alvin M. Weinberg,et al.  Criteria for scientific choice II: The two cultures , 1964 .

[19]  David F. Channell Pasteur's Quadrant: Basic Science and Technological Innovation , 1999 .