My purpose in the following paper is to consider whether the term "argument" should be extended to include pictures.(1) Clearly, a drawing or photograph independent of words can influence the thought and action of others; but can it, I wonder, argue? And if we say that it can, do we risk losing something important in our conventional understanding of argument? Below, I elaborate more fully what I mean by "conventional understanding of argument"; as for "picture," I define it here as any representation meant to look like the thing it represents. Thus, a sketch, drawing, painting, photograph, or three-dimensional model would be a "picture" if it were constructed to resemble imagined or actual objects in the visible world. Now, the concept of likeness has been much criticized of late; as Mitchell (1986) and others have pointed out, the picture is often (if not always) every bit as opaque and cultured as language. But without some notion of visible likeness, it is difficult to see how one would make sense of the everyday, and presumably useful, distinction between "showing" and "telling." I define "picture," then, as an artifact constructed to be iconic with the external world; and my question is, can such a thing, independent of language, be an "argument"? Many scholars are now convinced that the application of the word "argument" needs to be broadened. Willard (1989, p. 109), for example, has rejected the traditional association of the term with propositional discourse. Argument is interaction around incompatibility, he has written, and any attempt to distinguish it from other forms of persuasive communication is driven by "a bureaucratic rationale." Similarly, for Hesse (1992), all discourse is argumentative because all discourse is productive of belief. Narrative persuades because its "emplotment" of events over time engenders belief in acceptable sequences of action. It involves, that is, some propositions causing other propositions. At the same time, Hesse writes, what we have traditionally referred to as "argument" is itself a kind of narrative, a believable sequence of propositions plotted over time in such forms as the enthymeme. Fisher and Filloy (1982) agree. Although argument has typically been conceived in terms of inferential structures (claims and reasons), people also "arrive at conclusions based on 'dwelling-in' dramatic and literary works" (p. 343). The mode of arguing in such works is "suggestion": an immediate, emotional response becomes a reasoned belief through critical interpretation (p. 347). "Aesthetic" proofs, then, are those structures of suggestion which are invented by an author, experienced by an auditor, and used by a critic to substantiate a reasoned interpretation (p. 347). On this line of thought, it is hard not to see argument "everywhere," as Brockriede (1975, p. 179) had proposed. Couldn't a picture, by virtue of suggestion, engender belief in an argumentative sort of way? Yes, say Medhurst and DeSousa (1981), for whom political cartoons are a kind of enthymeme, relying on socially-sanctioned presuppositions to produce reasoned belief and action in others. Cartoons, that is, argue for political positions by adducing acceptable (albeit unspoken) reasons to hold those positions. Similarly, for Buchanan (1989, pp. 97, 107), arguments can inhere in things as well as words. When material objects solve problems in a reasonable manner, they are persuasive in the same way that verbal arguments are. Deliberation and use reveal the premises of such objects and arrange them into inferential structures. According to Buchanan, the Krups coffee mill, for example, is an "argument" for use and aesthetics over technology. Paintings are also susceptible to this kind of analysis. For Varga (1989), a 13th century painting of St. Francis of Assisi is a kind of argument; the portrait in the center is claim, and the narrative episodes flanking it are evidence for that claim: he who lived thus, who did these things, should be revered. …
[1]
Martin J. Medhurst,et al.
Political cartoons as rhetorical form: A taxonomy of graphic discourse
,
1981
.
[2]
E. Schiappa.
Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric
,
1991
.
[3]
Douglas Walton,et al.
Argument: The Logic of the Fallacies
,
1982
.
[4]
Ch. Perelman,et al.
The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation
,
1971
.
[5]
T. Govier.
A practical study of argument
,
1985
.
[6]
H. Becker.
Doing Things Together
,
1986
.
[7]
Richard Buchanan,et al.
Declaration by Design: Rhetoric, Argument, and Demonstration in Design Practice
,
1985
.
[8]
S. Langer.
Philosophy in a new key : a study in the symbolism of reason, rite, and art
,
1944
.
[9]
N. Postman,et al.
"Mix a Little Folly with Your Wisdom"--Horace@@@Children and Television.@@@Amusing Ourselves to Death: Public Discourse in the Age of Show Business.
,
1987
.
[10]
Aristotle,et al.
On rhetoric : a theory of civic discourse
,
1993
.
[11]
C. Wellman,et al.
Challenge and Response: Justification in Ethics
,
1971
.
[12]
William J. Mitchell,et al.
Iconology: Image, Text, Ideology
,
1986
.
[13]
George A. Kennedy,et al.
The Art of Persuasion in Greece
,
1963
.
[14]
D. Bryant.
Rhetoric: Its functions and its scope
,
1953
.
[15]
Nelson Goodman,et al.
Ways of Worldmaking
,
1979
.
[16]
Gary R. Orren,et al.
Eloquence in an Electronic Age: The Transformation of Political Speechmaking@@@The Electronic Commonwealth: The Impact of New Media Technologies on Democratic Politics
,
1988
.
[17]
D. O’Keefe.
The concepts of argument and arguing
,
1982
.
[18]
T. M. Robinson.
Contrasting Arguments: An edition of the Dissoi Logoi
,
1979
.
[19]
John Berger,et al.
Another Way Of Telling
,
1982
.
[20]
R. Moran.
Seeing and Believing: Metaphor, Image, and Force
,
1989,
Critical Inquiry.
[21]
Ch. Perelman.
The realm of rhetoric
,
1982
.
[22]
S. Toulmin.
The uses of argument
,
1960
.
[23]
K. Burke.
The rhetoric of religion : studies in logology
,
1962
.
[24]
Geoffrey Lloyd,et al.
Polarity and Analogy: Two Types of Argumentation in Early Greek Thought
,
1987
.
[25]
Rob Grootendorst,et al.
The Study of Argumentation.
,
1984
.
[26]
V. Margolin.
Design discourse : history, theory, criticism
,
1989
.
[27]
D. O’Keefe.
Two Concepts of Argument.
,
1977
.
[28]
G. Kerferd.
The sophistic movement
,
1981
.
[29]
Alec Fisher,et al.
The logic of real arguments: Philosophical assumptions
,
2004
.
[30]
Sol Worth,et al.
7. Pictures Can’t Say Ain’t
,
1981
.
[31]
Gotthold Ephraim Lessing,et al.
Laocoon: An Essay on the Limits of Painting and Poetry
,
1838
.
[32]
Donald N. McCloskey,et al.
Rhetoric Of The Human Sciences: Language And Argument In Scholarship And Public Affairs
,
1987
.
[33]
D. Kuhn.
THE SKILLS OF ARGUMENT
,
2008,
Education for Thinking.
[34]
A. Kibedi Varga,et al.
Criteria for Describing Word-and-Image Relations
,
1989
.
[35]
Michael Billig,et al.
Arguing and Thinking: A Rhetorical Approach to Social Psychology
,
1987
.
[36]
K. Burke,et al.
Language as symbolic action : essays on life, literature, and method
,
1966
.
[37]
C. Willard.
A theory of argumentation
,
1989
.
[38]
N. Goodman,et al.
Languages of art : an approach to a theory of symbols
,
1979
.
[39]
S. Jackson,et al.
Reconstructing Argumentative Discourse
,
1993
.
[40]
On Argument and Diagrams.
,
1978
.
[41]
Maurice A. Finocchiaro,et al.
Two Empirical Approaches to the Study of Reasoning
,
1994
.