What Is More Informative in the History of Science, the Signal or the Noise?

In many domains of knowledge, from mechanics (McCloskey, 1983) to thermodynamics (Wiser, 1987) to astronomy (Vosniadou & Brewer, 1992), it has been claimed that conceptual development in the individual resembles theory change in the history of science. Here, Kampourakis takes issue with that claim in the domain of evolution. In particular, he argues (a) that early evolutionary theorists never construed species as possessing essences and (b) that the distinction between pre-Darwinian and postDarwinian evolutionary thought is muddled and therefore an inappropriate analog for the development of evolutionary thought among today’s students of biology. (Kampourakis makes two additional arguments directed at Ware & Gelman, 2013; which I defer to Ware, this issue). My colleagues and I have argued that students’ evolutionary misconceptions resemble pre-Darwinian theories of evolution—in particular, the essentialist aspects of pre-Darwinian theories—on numerous occasions (Shtulman, 2006; Shtulman & Calabi, 2012, 2013; Shtulman & Checa, 2012; Shtulman & Schulz, 2008), and I maintain that this comparison is both empirically fruitful and theoretically meaningful. With respect to the first argument, Kampourakis notes that historians of science disagree about the veracity of the “Essentialism Story,” or the claim that Darwin’s predecessors and contemporaries essentialized biological kinds. “While it is true that scholars often wrote about the essences of life, of organs, etc.,” writes Kampourakis, “they never accepted that species had to have jointly necessary and severally sufficient conditions, or that members of a species should bear essential properties” (p. 1). Here, Kampourakis conflates two forms of essentialism: construing species in explicitly essentialist terms, which early evolutionary theorists arguably did not do, and positing theories of evolution that are inherently essentialist in their mechanisms of change, which early evolutionary theorists arguably did do (Gould, 1996; Hull, 1965; Mayr, 1982; Sober, 1980). That is,

[1]  J. Opfer,et al.  Cognitive foundations for science assessment design: Knowing what students know about evolution , 2012 .

[2]  Andrew Shtulman,et al.  Qualitative differences between naïve and scientific theories of evolution , 2006, Cognitive Psychology.

[3]  Medha Tare,et al.  A Conceptual Guide to Natural History Museum Visitors’ Understanding of Evolution , 2009 .

[4]  N. Pierce Origin of Species , 1914, Nature.

[5]  M. J. S. Hodge,et al.  Darwinism and Its Challengers@@@The Eclipse of Darwinism. Anti-Darwinian Evolution Theories in the Decades Around 1900. , 1985 .

[6]  Andrew Shtulman,et al.  Cognitive Constraints on the Understanding and Acceptance of Evolution , 2011 .

[7]  Susan A. Gelman,et al.  You Get What You Need: An Examination of Purpose-Based Inheritance Reasoning in Undergraduates, Preschoolers, and Biological Experts , 2014, Cogn. Sci..

[8]  Benjamin C. Heddy,et al.  Transforming Misconceptions: Using Transformative Experience to Promote Positive Affect and Conceptual Change in Students Learning about Biological Evolution. , 2013 .

[9]  John D. Coley,et al.  Common Origins of Diverse Misconceptions: Cognitive Principles and the Development of Biology Thinking , 2012, CBE life sciences education.

[10]  Andrew Shtulman,et al.  Parent-child conversations about evolution in the context of an interactive museum display , 2012 .

[11]  Patricia A. Ganea,et al.  Young Children Can Be Taught Basic Natural Selection Using a Picture-Storybook Intervention , 2014, Psychological science.

[12]  W. Brewer,et al.  Mental models of the earth: A study of conceptual change in childhood , 1992, Cognitive Psychology.

[13]  S. Gelman,et al.  "Two-Thousand Years of Stasis": How Psychological Essentialism Impedes Evolutionary Understa , 2012 .

[14]  E. Mayr The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution, and Inheritance , 1983 .

[15]  Andrew Shtulman,et al.  The Relation Between Essentialist Beliefs and Evolutionary Reasoning , 2008, Cogn. Sci..

[16]  Elliott Sober,et al.  Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism , 1980, Philosophy of Science.

[17]  Jonathan D. Lane,et al.  Anthropomorphizing Science: How Does It Affect the Development of Evolutionary Concepts? , 2013 .

[18]  Brandy N. Frazier,et al.  Changing Museum Visitors’ Conceptions of Evolution , 2012, Evolution: Education and Outreach.

[19]  Erin Marie Furtak,et al.  Linking a Learning Progression for Natural Selection to Teachers' Enactment of Formative Assessment. , 2012 .

[20]  Andrew Shtulman,et al.  Tuition vs. Intuition: Effects of Instruction on Naïve Theories of Evolution , 2013 .

[21]  T. Kuhn,et al.  The Structure of Scientific Revolutions , 1963 .

[22]  David L. Hull,et al.  THE EFFECT OF ESSENTIALISM ON TAXONOMY—TWO THOUSAND YEARS OF STASIS (I) * , 1965, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

[23]  K. Rosengren,et al.  Essentialist Reasoning and Knowledge Effects on Biological Reasoning in Young Children , 2013 .

[24]  Sarah K. Brem,et al.  Evolution challenges : integrating research and practice in teaching and learning about evolution , 2012 .

[25]  Charles Weijer,et al.  Full House: The Spread of Excellence from Plato to Darwin. , 1997 .

[26]  D. Nettle Understanding of Evolution May Be Improved by Thinking about People , 2010, Evolutionary psychology : an international journal of evolutionary approaches to psychology and behavior.