Towards a General Theory of Antirepresentationalism

This work represents an attempt to stake out the landscape for dynamicism based on a radical dismissal of the information-processing paradigm that dominates the philosophy of cognitive science. In Section 2, after setting up the basic toolkit of a theory of minimal representationalism, I introduce the central tenets of dynamic systems theory (DST) by discussing recent research in the dynamics of embodiment (Thelen et al. [2001]) in the perseverative-reaching literature. A recent proposal on the dynamics of representation—the dynamic field approach (Spencer and Schöner [2003])—according to which the alleged representational gap between DST and representational theories of cognition needs to be bridged in order to explain higher-order cognitive activity will then be reviewed. In Section 3 I shall argue that Spencer and Schöner's attempt to bridge the representational gap may jeopardize the whole (antirepresentationalist) spirit of the DST project. In order to show why, I shall introduce the key concepts of “reliability of environment” and “primagenesis”, and argue that DST can account for de-coupled, offline cognitive activity with no need of positing representational resources. Conclusions and directions for future research will follow. 1. Introduction 1.1. Minimal representationalism2. The Dynamic Field Approach 2.1. Dynamic systems theory and the continuity hypothesis2.2. The dynamic field approach: Bridging the representational gap?3. Towards a General Theory of Antirepresentationalism 3.1. Diagonal systems and microstimulated dissociations3.2. Reliability of environment and primagenesis3.3. Towards a general theory of antirepresentationalism4. Conclusion Introduction 1.1. Minimal representationalism Minimal representationalism The Dynamic Field Approach 2.1. Dynamic systems theory and the continuity hypothesis2.2. The dynamic field approach: Bridging the representational gap? Dynamic systems theory and the continuity hypothesis The dynamic field approach: Bridging the representational gap? Towards a General Theory of Antirepresentationalism 3.1. Diagonal systems and microstimulated dissociations3.2. Reliability of environment and primagenesis3.3. Towards a general theory of antirepresentationalism Diagonal systems and microstimulated dissociations Reliability of environment and primagenesis Towards a general theory of antirepresentationalism Conclusion

[1]  A. Clark,et al.  Genic Representation: Reconciling Content and Causal Complexity , 1999, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

[2]  Charles Wallis,et al.  Computation and cognition , 2003, J. Exp. Theor. Artif. Intell..

[3]  P. Calvo,et al.  DIRECTIONS FOR AN EMBODIED COGNITIVE SCIENCE: TOWARDS AN INTEGRATED APPROACH , 2008 .

[4]  Pietro G. Morasso,et al.  Self-Organization, Computational Maps, and Motor Control , 1997 .

[5]  J. Bickle Philosophy and Neuroscience , 2003 .

[6]  A. Clark Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again , 1996 .

[7]  Rick Grush,et al.  The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception , 2004, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[8]  M. Steriade The Mind-Brain Continuum edited by Rodolfo Llinás and Patricia S. Churchland, MIT Press, 1996. $50.00 (xi + 315 pages) ISBN 0 262 12198 0 , 1997, Trends in Neurosciences.

[9]  E. Thelen,et al.  Connectionism and dynamic systems: are they really different? , 2003 .

[10]  William Bechtel,et al.  Representations and Cognitive Explanations: Assessing the Dynamicist's Challenge in Cognitive Science , 1998, Cogn. Sci..

[11]  J. Piaget The construction of reality in the child , 1954 .

[12]  Francisco Calvo Garzóan,et al.  Connectionist Semantics and the Collateral Information Challenge , 2003 .

[13]  W. Newsome,et al.  Somatosensation: Touching the mind’s fingers , 2000, Current Biology.

[14]  Walter J. Freeman,et al.  Neurodynamics: An Exploration in Mesoscopic Brain Dynamics , 2000, Perspectives in Neural Computing.

[15]  Francisco Calvo Garzón Context-free versus Context-Dependent Constituency Relations: A False Dichotomy , 2004, AAAI Technical Report.

[16]  Francisco Calvo Garzón Issues of implementation matter for representation , 2004 .

[17]  Marco Giunti,et al.  Computation, Dynamics, and Cognition , 2001 .

[18]  Gavan Lintern,et al.  Dynamic patterns: The self-organization of brain and behavior , 1997, Complex.

[19]  Andy Clark,et al.  Reasons, robots and the extended mind , 2001 .

[20]  Matthias Scheutz,et al.  Computationalism: New Directions , 2003 .

[21]  Andy Clark,et al.  Doing without representing? , 1994, Synthese.

[22]  A. Markman,et al.  Extending the classical view of representation , 2000, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[23]  T. Gelder,et al.  The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science , 1998, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[24]  G. Schöner,et al.  Bridging the representational gap in the dynamic systems approach to development , 2003 .

[25]  T. Gelder,et al.  What Might Cognition Be, If Not Computation? , 1995 .

[26]  W. Newsome,et al.  Microstimulation in visual area MT: effects on direction discrimination performance , 1992, The Journal of neuroscience : the official journal of the Society for Neuroscience.

[27]  A. Markman,et al.  In Defense of Representation , 2000, Cognitive Psychology.

[28]  Iris Berent,et al.  Are There Limits to Statistical Learning? , 2003, Science.

[29]  Andy Clark,et al.  Towards a Cognitive Robotics , 1999, Adapt. Behav..

[30]  Daniel His-wen Liu Reconsidering the Notion of Dynamical Systems Theory Resources as a Conceptual Framework , 2003 .

[31]  R. Desimone,et al.  Neural Mechanisms of Visual Working Memory in Prefrontal Cortex of the Macaque , 1996, The Journal of Neuroscience.

[32]  Arthur B. Markman,et al.  Discrete thoughts: Why cognition must use discrete representations , 2003 .

[33]  E. Thelen,et al.  The dynamics of embodiment: A field theory of infant perseverative reaching , 2001, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[34]  G. Schöner,et al.  Dynamic Field Theory of Movement Preparation , 2022 .