Classical Questions, Radical Answers: Connectionism and the Structure of Mental Representations

The many and obvious contrasts between Connectionism and (something like) “most other work in Cognitive Science” often give rise to rather grandiose talk of scientific upheaval. Thus it is common to hear the proposal that Connectionism represents (or is the beginning of, or at least points in the general direction of) a whole new approach and perhaps even a whole new paradigm in the study of cognition, an approach which directly contests and may even be displacing (something like) the dominant symbolic view. This is an exciting prospect, especially for those philosophers and others who prefer to view such topics as artificial intelligence and cognitive psychology in terms of the grand sweep of intellectual history. Unfortunately, despite the endless tabloid observations, nobody yet seems altogether sure just what Connectionism is, in any sense going beyond the standard fare of dull details and techno-truisms about the nature of typical Connectionist networks. Indeed, in discussion to date there is very little agreement even over how the phenomenon itself is best described: some regard Connectionism as nothing less than a whole new paradigm, while others-using progressively more vague terminology-have described it as a radically new architecture, theory, framework, model, approach, and simply as a new view.

[1]  Allen Newell,et al.  Computer science as empirical inquiry: symbols and search , 1976, CACM.

[2]  W. Bechtel What Happens to Accounts of Mind-Brain Relations If We Forego an Architecture of Rules and Representations? , 1986, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

[3]  Tim van Gelder,et al.  Compositionality: A Connectionist Variation on a Classical Theme , 1990, Cogn. Sci..

[4]  P. Smolensky On variable binding and the representation of symbolic structures in connectionist systems , 1987 .

[5]  P. Smolensky On the proper treatment of connectionism , 1988, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[6]  R. Brandom Singular Terms and Sentential Sign Designs , 1987 .

[7]  Adrian Cussins,et al.  The Connectionist Construction of Concepts , 1990, The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence.

[8]  William Bechtel,et al.  CONTEMPORARY CONNECTIONISM: ARE THE NEW PARALLEL DISTRIBUTED PROCESSING MODELS COGNITIVE OR ASSOCIATIONIST? , 1985 .

[9]  Zenon W. Pylyshyn,et al.  Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis , 1988, Cognition.

[10]  T. Kuhn,et al.  The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. , 1964 .

[11]  Geoffrey E. Hinton,et al.  Distributed Representations , 1986, The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence.

[12]  John Haugeland,et al.  Artificial intelligence - the very idea , 1987 .

[13]  John Haugeland The nature and plausibility of Cognitivism , 1978, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[14]  W. Freeman Second Commentary: On the proper treatment of connectionism by Paul Smolensky (1988) - Neuromachismo Rekindled , 1989 .

[15]  R. M. Harnish,et al.  The Representation of knowledge and belief , 1986 .

[16]  Zenon W. Pylyshyn,et al.  Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science , 1984 .

[17]  J. Fodor The Language of Thought , 1980 .

[18]  T. Horgan,et al.  Representations without Rules , 1989 .

[19]  J. Fodor,et al.  Connectionism and the problem of systematicity: Why Smolensky's solution doesn't work , 1990, Cognition.

[20]  Jordan B. Pollack,et al.  Recursive Distributed Representations , 1990, Artif. Intell..

[21]  J. Elman Representation and structure in connectionist models , 1991 .