Scientific progress as increasing verisimilitude.

According to the foundationalist picture, shared by many rationalists and positivist empiricists, science makes cognitive progress by accumulating justified truths. Fallibilists, who point out that complete certainty cannot be achieved in empirical science, can still argue that even successions of false theories may progress toward the truth. This proposal was supported by Karl Popper with his notion of truthlikeness or verisimilitude. Popper's own technical definition failed, but the idea that scientific progress means increasing truthlikeness can be expressed by defining degrees of truthlikeness in terms of similarities between states of affairs. This paper defends the verisimilitude approach against Alexander Bird who argues that the "semantic" definition (in terms of truth or truthlikeness alone) is not sufficient to define progress, but the "epistemic" definition referring to justification and knowledge is more adequate. Here Bird ignores the crucial distinction between real progress and estimated progress, explicated by the difference between absolute (and usually unknown) degrees of truthlikeness and their evidence-relative expected values. Further, it is argued that Bird's idea of returning to the cumulative model of growth requires an implausible trick of transforming past false theories into true ones.

[1]  Ilkka Niiniluoto,et al.  Critical Scientific Realism , 1999 .

[2]  H. Hettema,et al.  Sommerfeld’s A tombau : a case study in potential truth approximation , 1995 .

[3]  I. A. Kieseppä Truthlikeness for Multidimensional, Quantitative Cognitive Problems , 1996 .

[4]  J. Barrett Approximate Truth and Descriptive Nesting , 2008 .

[5]  A. Goldman Knowledge in a Social World , 1999 .

[6]  P. Kleingeld,et al.  The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , 2013 .

[7]  Peter Gärdenfors,et al.  Knowledge in Flux: Modeling the Dynamics of Epistemic States , 2008 .

[8]  Darrell P. Rowbottom What Scientific Progress Is Not: Against Bird’s Epistemic View , 2010 .

[9]  Larry Laudan,et al.  Science and Values: The Aims of Science and Their Role in Scientific Debate , 1984 .

[10]  K. Popper,et al.  Conjectures and refutations;: The growth of scientific knowledge , 1972 .

[11]  A. Bird Scientific progress as accumulation of knowledge: a reply to Rowbottom , 2008 .

[12]  T. Kuipers From Instrumentalism to Constructive Realism: On Some Relations between Confirmation, Empirical Progress, and Truth Approximation , 2000 .

[13]  J. Z. Bonilla,et al.  Truthlikeness without truth: A methodological approach , 1992, Synthese.

[14]  E. Barnes Beyond verisimilitude: A linguistically invariant basis for scientific progress , 1991, Synthese.

[15]  L. Laudan Science as Problem-Solving. (Book Reviews: Progress and Its Problems. Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth) , 1977 .

[16]  Eileen Cornell Way,et al.  Realism Rescued: How Scientific Progress Is Possible , 1995 .

[17]  Bernard Barber,et al.  The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. , 1963 .

[18]  Ilkka Niiniluoto,et al.  Is Science Progressive , 1984 .

[19]  G. Oddie Likeness to Truth , 1986 .

[20]  K. Popper Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach , 1972 .

[21]  G. Cevolani,et al.  Progress as Approximation to the Truth: A Defence of the Verisimilitudinarian Approach , 2013 .

[22]  Leszek Nowak,et al.  The structure of idealization , 1979 .

[23]  Alexander J Bird,et al.  What Is Scientific Progress , 2007 .

[24]  I. Niiniluoto Revising Beliefs Towards the Truth , 2011 .

[25]  Darrell P. Rowbottom N-rays and the semantic view of scientific progress , 2008 .

[26]  Isaac Levi Estimation and error free information , 2004, Synthese.

[27]  M. Birattari,et al.  A Critique of the Constitutive Role of Truthlikeness in the Similarity Approach , 2010 .