It is generally assumed that the "lexical component" of a grammar may be treated on the analogue of the syntac tic and phonological components, as a device that pairs words with specifications of the things and classes of things that they can normally be used to refer to; if an item can be used to refer to more than one extension, then, it must be accorded more than one lexical entry. We begin by showing how these assumptions come to grief over the prob lems posed by the phenomenon of polysemy, when one word, like chicken, is used to refer at one time to a kind of bird and at another to a kind of meat. It is argued, first that the inclusion of multiple lexical entries leads to undesirable complications in the syntax, and second that pragmatic schemata that generate multiple uses must be inde pendently available, since the same phenomena appear in ostensive reference. An account of "deferred ostension" is presented, in which it is shown why you can point at some things to identify others; this account is then extended to the multiple uses of "descriptive terms." We proceed to argue that with descriptions, there is no way to tell which of the uses of a word is specified by the rules of language, either in practice or in principle; the semantics/pragmatics distinction cannot be drawn. In that case, we argue, the idealization to the knowledge of the ideal speaker-listener in a perfectly homogeneous speech-community is considerably more pernicious for semantics than for syntax or phonology, as we must pre sume as well a community in which extralinguistic beliefs and practices are uniform. We conclude that it is more reasonable to describe the speaker's knowledge of wordmeanings as part of his knowledge of the (heterogeneous) collective beliefs of the community, which we can idealize as his "system of normal beliefs," borrowing our model from game theory. Against this idealization, we show, it is possible to explain a number of disparate linguistic phenom ena, such as speaker judgments that some word uses are "acceptable," the phenomena associated with "partial moti vation," metaphorical word-uses, and change in meaning. Adviser: Professor D. Terence Langendoen Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
[1]
R. Trench.
English, past and present
,
1881
.
[2]
Otto Jespersen,et al.
The Philosophy of Grammar
,
1924
.
[3]
Benny Goodman,et al.
The kingdom of swing
,
1939
.
[4]
P. Christophersen.
The articles : A study of their theory and use in English
,
1940
.
[5]
C. F. Hockett.
A Course in Modern Linguistics
,
1959
.
[6]
R. Lees.
The grammar of English nominalizations
,
1960
.
[7]
J. Fodor,et al.
The structure of a semantic theory
,
1963
.
[8]
J. Katz.
Semantic Theory and the Meaning of 'Good'
,
1964
.
[9]
Noam Chomsky,et al.
वाक्यविन्यास का सैद्धान्तिक पक्ष = Aspects of the theory of syntax
,
1965
.
[10]
Noam Chomsky,et al.
Remarks on Nominalization
,
2020,
Nominalization.
[11]
D. Bolinger,et al.
语言要略 = Aspects of Language
,
1968
.
[12]
H. Pleasants.
Serious Music--and All That Jazz! : An Adventure in Music Criticism
,
1969
.
[13]
Geoffrey Leech,et al.
Towards a semantic description of English
,
1969
.
[14]
Uriel Weinreich,et al.
Explorations in semantic theory
,
1972
.
[15]
Ann Borkin.
Coreference and beheaded NP's
,
1972
.
[16]
Georgia M. Green,et al.
Semantics and Syntactic Regularity
,
1974
.
[17]
William M. Waite,et al.
Semantic Analysis
,
1976,
International Conference on Compiler Construction.
[18]
Mark Aronoff,et al.
Word Formation in Generative Grammar
,
1979
.
[19]
G. Miller,et al.
Language and Perception
,
1976
.
[20]
Michael Don Palmer,et al.
Reflections on language
,
1977
.
[21]
D Wilson,et al.
Propositional Structure and Illocutionary Force
,
1979
.
[22]
Lars Hermerén,et al.
Meaning and form
,
1980
.