Presupposition theory within the dynamic semantics paradigm has been characterized by three developments: the systematization of the projection facts and the conceptual explanation in terms of context change, the development of representational means and algorithms in discourse representation theory, and the emphasis of the semantic foundations within dynamic semantics.
The first development is constituted by Karttunen (1973), Karttunen (1974) and Stalnaker (1974) and Heim (1983b). Kamp and Rosdeutscher (1994b), Kamp and Rosdeutscher (1994a) have created DRT representations and coined the term presupposition justification, while van der Sandt (1992) has developed an algorithm for treating presuppositions.
An extensive exposition of this second development is in Geurts (1999).
The third development is the application of techniques from dynamic semantics to presupposition (Beaver 1995b), (Beaver 1997) and van Rooy (1997) and builds on dynamic predicate logic (Groenendijk and Stokhof 1991, Dekker 1993).
The first development has led to detailed descriptive observations in Karttunen (1974) and to great conceptual clarity in Stalnaker (1974), but was not yet embedded in a semantic formalism which directly expresses the underlying ideas, which would be very important for the purposes of computational linguistics and for the integration with other areas of semantic theory.
The second development has led to operational models of presupposition justification and to good empirical coverage. The model-theoretic interpretation of presuppositions seems to have been slightly neglected in this approach. The question whether the representational operations employed in the algorithms have a semantic or logical justification was not always pursued consequently.
The third development can be understood as a reaction against this tendency. Because of the renewed emphasis on the model-theoretic interpretation of presuppositions, it has resulted in detailed expositions and refinements of the so-called satisfaction model of presupposition, in particular to an eliminative semantics for the presupposition operator within a generalized dynamic semantics using epistemic alternatives (Beaver 1995b). This revival of the semantic basis of presupposition theory has also led to new two-dimensional analyses of presuppositions (van Rooy 1997), and to an interest in the question how dynamic semantics analyses of presuppositions and analyses based on partial logic relate to each other (Krahmer 1998)1. With respect to empirical coverage and algorithmic realization, these new satisfaction models do not significantly improve on the discourse representation theory treatment.
In addition to these developments within presupposition theory, the work on semantic formalisms in dynamic semantics has led to dynamic predicate logic (Groenendijk and Stokhof 1991) and a version of it which is - through the use of partial variable assignments - closer to the framework in which Heim (1983b) formulated her analysis of presuppositions and to original DRT (Kamp 1981). But this work on semantic formalisms concentrated on first-order fragments without a presupposition operator. The result were mathematically precise reconstructions of the semantic machinery underlying the dynamics of interpretation. The other main ingredient in the analysis of Heim (1983b), namely the semi-pragmatic accommodation mechanism, was not reconstructed in these formal models.
In this situation, it was desirable to develop a theory of presupposition which integrates semantic foundations with an algorithmic treatment. A semantically well-founded algorithm is usually one which is based on logical inference. Attempts to analyze presuppositions as semantic entailment in first-order logic have met with difficulties, however. So another way of understanding presuppositional reasoning as based on logical inference was needed.
Such an idea came up in the artificial intelligence literature, at least for the treatment of certain expressions that linguists classify as presuppositonal, in particular definite descriptions (Hobbs, Stickel, Appelt and Martin 1993). Hobbs proposed to use abductive reasoning quite generally to model text comprehension. The presuppositions of definite descriptions must be proved abductively from the context. The logical language was however not equipped with a dynamic semantics.
David Beaver has argued for the relevance of this approach for semantics. Beaver emphasized the need for a possibility to let presuppositions interact with commonsense reasoning by giving examples in which two sentences with the same syntactic form, but different lexical entries can give rise to different perceived presuppositions because of the different plausibilities of the possible presuppositions.
Diese Arbeit betrifft die Prasuppositionstheorie und ihre computerlinguistische Umsetzung. Ein semantischer Formalismus aus dem Bereich der dynamischen Semantik wird so um Konstrukte zur Reprasentation von Prasuppositionen erweitert, dass die prasuppositionale Inferenz als abduktive Inferenz dargestellt werden kann. Die theoretischen Vorschlage sind implementierungsnah formuliert, um eine unmittelbare computerlinguistische Umsetzung zu ermoglichen.
Die Arbeit hat zwei Hauptthemen aus dem Bereich der Prasuppositionstheorie. Das erste Thema ist die Anwendung der abduktiven Inferenz auf das Problem der Rechtfertigung von Prasuppositionen, das zweite Thema sind die Einzigkeitsbedingungen von definiten Kennzeichnungen. Das erste Thema wird in den Kapiteln 1, 2 und 3 behandelt, das zweite Thema in den Kapiteln 4 und 5. Diese Reihenfolge ergibt sich aus der Natur der Sache, da die vorgestellte Theorie zu Einzigkeitsbedingungen auf eine Theorie der Prasuppositionsrechtfertigung Bezug nehmen mus. Die Grundidee dieser Theorie konnte wohl auch mit Hilfe anderer Prasuppositionstheorien ausgedruckt werden, im Rahmen dieser Arbeit war es jedoch naturlich, die in den Kapiteln 1 bis 3 vorgestellte abduktionsbasierte Analyse zu verwenden, weil dort wichtige Grundbegriffe explizit definiert werden, die in anderen Analysen oft nicht bereitgestellt werden.
[1]
P. Christophersen.
The articles : A study of their theory and use in English
,
1940
.
[2]
B. V. Fraassen.
Singular Terms, Truth-Value Gaps, and Free Logic
,
1966
.
[3]
James D. McCawley,et al.
Where do noun phrases come from
,
1969
.
[4]
G. Harman.
Deep Structure as Logical Form
,
1970
.
[5]
LAURI KARTTUNEN,et al.
PRESUPPOSITION AND LINGUISTIC CONTEXT
,
1974
.
[6]
Ruth Kempson,et al.
Presupposition and the delimitation of semantics
,
1975
.
[7]
Pauline Jacobson,et al.
The syntax of crossing coreference sentences
,
1977
.
[8]
Saul A. Kripke,et al.
Naming and Necessity
,
1980
.
[9]
Irene Heim,et al.
The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases : a dissertation
,
1982
.
[10]
P. Sells.
Restrictive and non-restrictive modification
,
1985
.
[11]
Mats Rooth.
Noun Phrase Interpretation in Montague Grammar, File Change Semantics, and Situation Semantics
,
1987
.
[12]
David Makinson,et al.
On the status of the postulate of recovery in the logic of theory change
,
1987,
J. Philos. Log..
[13]
John Wylie Lloyd,et al.
Foundations of Logic Programming
,
1987,
Symbolic Computation.
[14]
Patrick Saint-Dizier,et al.
Review of Prolog and natural-language analysis: CSLI lecture notes 10 by Fernando C. N. Pereira and Stuart M. Shieber. Center for the Study of Language and Information 1987.
,
1988
.
[15]
Michael Hess,et al.
Crossing Coreference in Discourse Representation Theory
,
1988,
COLING.
[16]
Nicholas John Haddock.
Incremental semantics and interactive syntactic processing
,
1988
.
[17]
Robert Dale,et al.
Generating referring expressions in a domain of objects and processes (language representation)
,
1988
.
[18]
D. Over,et al.
Studies in the Way of Words.
,
1989
.
[19]
Henk Zeevat,et al.
A compositional approach to discourse representation theory
,
1989
.
[20]
Kees van Deemter.
Forward References in Natural Language
,
1990,
J. Semant..
[21]
J. Delin,et al.
Cleft constructions in discourse.
,
1990
.
[22]
Paolo Mancarella,et al.
Abductive Logic Programming
,
1992,
LPNMR.
[23]
Jeroen Groenendijk,et al.
Dynamic predicate logic
,
1991
.
[24]
Rob A. van der Sandt,et al.
Presupposition Projection as Anaphora Resolution
,
1992,
J. Semant..
[25]
Irene Heim,et al.
Presupposition Projection and the Semantics of Attitude Verbs
,
1992,
J. Semant..
[26]
Kees van Deemter.
Towards a Generalization of Anaphora
,
1992,
J. Semant..
[27]
Henk Zeevat,et al.
Presupposition and Accommodation in Update Semantics
,
1992,
J. Semant..
[28]
Uwe Reyle,et al.
Dealing with Ambiguities by Underspecification: Construction, Representation and Deduction
,
1993,
J. Semant..
[29]
Peter Lasersohn,et al.
Existence Presuppositions and Background Knowledge
,
1993,
J. Semant..
[30]
Jerry R. Hobbs,et al.
Interpretation as Abduction
,
1993,
Artif. Intell..
[31]
Nicholas Asher,et al.
Reference to abstract objects in discourse
,
1993,
Studies in linguistics and philosophy.
[32]
Jan van Eijck,et al.
The Dynamics of Description
,
1993,
J. Semant..
[33]
Uwe Reyle,et al.
From discourse to logic
,
1993
.
[34]
C. F. M. Vermeulen,et al.
Sequence semantics for dynamic predicate logic
,
1993,
J. Log. Lang. Inf..
[35]
HANS KAMP,et al.
DRS-CONSTRUCTION AND LEXICALLY DRIVEN INFERENCE
,
1994
.
[36]
C.F.M. Vermeulen.
Explorations of the dynamic environment
,
1994
.
[37]
Knud Lambrecht,et al.
Information structure and sentence form
,
1994
.
[38]
Dov M. Gabbay,et al.
Labelled abduction and relevance reasoning
,
1994
.
[39]
P. Dekker.
Predicate logic with anaphora
,
1994
.
[40]
Paul Buitelaar,et al.
Bridging as Coercive Accommodation
,
1995,
ArXiv.
[41]
Emiel Krahmer,et al.
Negation and Disjunction in Discourse Representation Theory
,
1995,
J. Semant..
[42]
Robert Dale,et al.
Computational Interpretations of the Gricean Maxims in the Generation of Referring Expressions
,
1995,
Cogn. Sci..
[43]
J. Groenendijk,et al.
Coreference and modality
,
1996
.
[44]
Uwe Reyle,et al.
A calculus for first order Discourse Representation Structures
,
1996,
J. Log. Lang. Inf..
[45]
Kjell Johan Saeboe.
Anaphoric presuppositions and zero anaphora
,
1996
.
[46]
Frank Veltman,et al.
Defaults in update semantics
,
1996,
J. Philos. Log..
[47]
Paul Dekker,et al.
The values of variables in dynamic semantics
,
1996
.
[48]
Bart Geurts,et al.
Local satisfaction guaranteed: A presupposition theory and its problems
,
1996
.
[49]
Jan van Eijck,et al.
Representing Discourse in Context
,
1997,
Handbook of Logic and Language.
[50]
Anatoli Strigin,et al.
Lexical Rules As Hypotheses Generators
,
1998,
J. Semant..
[51]
Emiel Krahmer,et al.
On the Interpretation of Anaphoric Noun Phrases: Towards a Full Understanding of Partial Matches
,
1998,
J. Semant..
[52]
Matthew Stone,et al.
Textual Economy Through Close Coupling of Syntax and Semantics
,
1998,
INLG.
[53]
Alex Lascarides,et al.
The Semantics and Pragmatics of Presupposition
,
1998,
J. Semant..
[54]
Matthew Stone.
Modality in dialogue: planning, pragmatics and computation
,
1998
.
[55]
Kai von Fintel,et al.
NPI Licensing, Strawson Entailment, and Context Dependency
,
1999,
J. Semant..
[56]
Gosse Bouma.
Recensie van "Corblin, francis; Godard, Danièle and Marandin, Jean-Marie (eds). Empirical Issues in Formal Syntax and Semantics, Selected Papers from the Colloque de Syntaxe et de Sémantique de Paris (CSSP 1995), Peter Lang, Bern, 1997.''
,
1999
.
[57]
Pauline Jacobson.
Paycheck Pronouns, Bach-Peters Sentences, and Variable-Free Semantics
,
2000
.
[58]
K. Fintel.
Would You Believe It? The King of France is Back! (Presuppositions and Truth-Value Intuitions)
,
2001
.