Implicatures and discourse structure

One of the characteristic marks of Gricean implicatures in general, and scalar implicatures in particular, examples of which are given in (1), is that they are the result of a defeasible inference. (1a) John had some of the cookies (1b)John had some of the cookies. In fact he had them all. (1a) invites the inference that John didn't have all the cookies,an inference that can be defeated by additional information, as in (1b). Scalar inferences like that in (1a) thus depend upon some sort of nonmonotonic reasoning over semantic contents. They share this characteristic of defeasiblility with inferences that result in the presence of discourse relations that link discourse segments together into a discourse structure for a coherent text or dialogue---call these inferences discourse or D inferences. I have studied these inferences about discourse structure, their effects on content and how they are computed in the theory known as Segmented Discourse Representation Theory or SDRT. In this paper I investigate how the tools used to infer discourse relations apply to what Griceans and others call scalar or quantity implicatures. The benefits of this investigation are three fold: at the theoretical level, we have a unified and relatively simple framework for computing defeasible inferences both of the quantity and discourse structure varieties; further, we can capture what ' s right about the intuitions of so called "localist" views about scalar implicatures; finally, this framework permits us to investigate how D-inferences and scalar inferences might interact, in particular how discourse structure might trigger scalar inferences, thus explaining the variability(Chemla, 2008) or even non-existence of embedded implicatures noted recently (e.g., Geurts and Pouscoulous, 2009), and their occasional noncancellability. The view of scalar inferences that emerges from this study is also rather different from the way both localists and Neo- Griceans conceive of them. Both localists and Neo-Griceans view implicatures as emerging from pragmatic reasoning processes that are strictly separated from the calculation of semantic values; where they differ is at what level the pragmatic implicatures are calculated. Localists take them to be calculated in parallel with semantic composition, whereas Neo-Griceans take them to have as input the complete semantic content of the assertion. My view is that scalar inferences depend on discourse structure and large view of semantic content in which semantics and pragmatics interact in a complex way to produce an interpretation of an utterance or a discourse.

[1]  Daniel Hardt,et al.  Discourse parallelism, ellipsis, and ambiguity , 2001, J. Semant..

[2]  G. Chierchia,et al.  The Grammatical View of Scalar Implicatures and the Relationship between Semantics and Pragmatics , 2008 .

[3]  Indra Dewi Ienneke,et al.  PRESUPPOSITIONS AND IMPLICATURES , 2008 .

[4]  Benjamin Spector Aspects de la pragmatique des opérateurs logiques , 2006 .

[5]  Daniel Hardt,et al.  Ellipsis and the Structure of Discourse , 2004, J. Semant..

[6]  Alex Lascarides,et al.  The Semantics and Pragmatics of Presupposition , 1998, J. Semant..

[7]  Nicholas Asher,et al.  Dynamic Discourse Semantics for Embedded Speech Acts , 2006, JSAI Workshops.

[8]  Nicholas Asher,et al.  SDRT and Continuation Semantics , 2010, JSAI-isAI Workshops.

[9]  Chungmin Lee Information Structure in PA/SN or Descriptive/ Metalinguistic Negation: With Reference to Scalar Implicatures1 , 2009 .

[10]  Bart Geurts,et al.  Scalar implicature and local pragmatics. , 2009 .

[11]  Jeffrey L. Elman,et al.  Coherence and Coreference Revisited , 2007, J. Semant..

[12]  Robert van Rooij,et al.  Pragmatic Meaning and Non-monotonic Reasoning: The Case of Exhaustive Interpretation , 2006 .

[13]  Daniel Hardt,et al.  Discourse Parallelism, Scope, and Ellipsis , 1997 .

[14]  F. Récanati Embedded Implicatures , 2022 .

[15]  Nicholas Asher,et al.  Free Choice Permission is Strong Permission , 2005, Synthese.

[16]  K. Schulz,et al.  Minimal models in semantics and pragmatics : free choice, exhaustivity, and conditionals , 2007 .

[17]  E. Chemla Universal Implicatures and Free Choice Effects: Experimental Data , 2009 .

[18]  Laure Vieu,et al.  Locating adverbials in discourse , 2005, Journal of French Language Studies.

[19]  Arjen Zondervan,et al.  Scalar implicatures or focus: an experimental approach , 2010 .

[20]  Nicholas Asher,et al.  Commonsense Entailment: A Modal Theory of Non-monotonic Reasoning , 1991, IJCAI.

[21]  Katrin Schulz,et al.  Exhaustive Interpretation of Complex Sentences , 2004, J. Log. Lang. Inf..

[22]  Friederike Moltmann,et al.  Nonreferential Complements, Nominalizations, and Derived Objects , 2004, J. Semant..

[23]  Ken Turner,et al.  Current research in the semantics/pragmatics interface , 1999 .

[24]  John W. Du Bois Discourse and Grammar , 2014 .

[25]  Nicholas Asher,et al.  Reference to abstract objects in discourse , 1993, Studies in linguistics and philosophy.

[26]  Andreas Herzig,et al.  Conditionals: from philosophy to computer science , 1996 .

[27]  Alex Lascarides,et al.  Temporal interpretation, discourse relations and commonsense entailment , 1993, The Language of Time - A Reader.

[28]  Benjamin Spector 10: Scalar Implicatures: Exhaustivity and Gricean Reasoning , 2007 .

[29]  Alex Lascarides,et al.  Logics of Conversation , 2005, Studies in natural language processing.

[30]  Nicholas Asher Troubles on the right frontier , 2008 .

[31]  Uli Sauerland,et al.  Scalar Implicatures in Complex Sentences , 2004 .

[32]  M. Meyerhoff,et al.  Working papers in linguistics , 1994 .

[33]  Nicholas Asher Implicatures in Discourse , 2009 .

[34]  D. Fox,et al.  On the characterization of alternatives , 2011 .

[35]  Roger Schwarzschild,et al.  GIVENNESS, AVOIDF AND OTHER CONSTRAINTS ON THE PLACEMENT OF ACCENT* , 1999 .

[36]  Craige Roberts,et al.  Information Structure: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics , 2012 .