The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology the Need to Explain

How do reasoners deal with inconsistencies? James (1907) believed that the rational solution is to revise your beliefs and to do so in a minimal way. We propose an alternative: You explain the origins of an inconsistency, which has the side effect of a revision to your beliefs. This hypothesis predicts that individuals should spontaneously create explanations of inconsistencies rather than refute one of the assertions and that they should rate explanations as more probable than refutations. A pilot study showed that participants spontaneously explain inconsistencies when they are asked what follows from inconsistent premises. In three subsequent experiments, participants were asked to compare explanations of inconsistencies against minimal refutations of the inconsistent premises. In Experiment 1, participants chose which conclusion was most probable; in Experiment 2 they rank ordered the conclusions based on their probability; and in Experiment 3 they estimated the mean probability of the conclusions' occurrence. In all three studies, participants rated explanations as more probable than refutations. The results imply that individuals create explanations to resolve an inconsistency and that these explanations lead to changes in belief. Changes in belief are therefore of secondary importance to the primary goal of explanation.

[1]  J. Hayes,et al.  The importance of universal quantifiers in a hypothetical reasoning task , 1971 .

[2]  G. d'Ydewalle,et al.  Initial belief state as a predictor of belief revision , 2000 .

[3]  P. Johnson-Laird How We Reason , 2006 .

[4]  M. Gelfand The pursuit of truth. , 1980, South African medical journal = Suid-Afrikaanse tydskrif vir geneeskunde.

[5]  R. Catrambone,et al.  Proceedings of the 32nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society , 2010 .

[6]  S. Tipper,et al.  Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology , 1948, Nature.

[7]  N. Chater,et al.  Conditional inference and constraint satisfaction: Reconciling mental models and the probabilistic approach? , 2010 .

[8]  Tiago Villanueva,et al.  All the president's men , 2004, BMJ.

[9]  H. Wellman,et al.  Inconsistency with prior knowledge triggers children's causal explanatory reasoning. , 2010, Child development.

[10]  W. Ahn,et al.  Effect of theory-based feature correlations on typicality judgments , 2002, Memory & cognition.

[11]  Michelene T. H. Chi,et al.  Eliciting Self-Explanations Improves Understanding , 1994, Cogn. Sci..

[12]  H. Kyburg The Fixation of Belief and Its Undoing , 1994 .

[13]  Edward Mackinnon Aspects of Scientific Explanation: and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science , 1967 .

[14]  W. Salmon Four decades of scientific explanation , 1989 .

[15]  Ruth M. J. Byrne,et al.  Everyday Reasoning with Conditional Sequences , 1989 .

[16]  Denise Dellarosa Cummins,et al.  Naive theories and causal deduction , 1995, Memory & cognition.

[17]  C. Judd,et al.  Pragmatism. A new name for some old ways of thinking. , 1908 .

[18]  T. Lombrozo,et al.  Simplicity and probability in causal explanation , 2007, Cognitive Psychology.

[19]  R. Hastie,et al.  The moderating influence of variability on belief revision , 1996, Psychonomic bulletin & review.

[20]  Nick Chater,et al.  Cognition and Conditionals: Probability and Logic in Human Thinking , 2010 .

[21]  Peter Gärdenfors,et al.  Epistemic importance and minimal changes of belief , 1984 .

[22]  Renée Elio,et al.  Belief Change as Propositional Update , 1997, Cogn. Sci..

[23]  P N Johnson-Laird,et al.  Hidden conflicts: explanations make inconsistencies harder to detect. , 2012, Acta psychologica.

[24]  G. Politzer,et al.  Belief revision and uncertain reasoning , 2001 .

[25]  Robert Stalnaker A causal theory of counterfactuals , 2004 .

[26]  Peter Gärdenfors,et al.  Knowledge in Flux: Modeling the Dynamics of Epistemic States , 2008 .

[27]  F. Keil,et al.  Explanation and understanding , 2015 .

[28]  H. Price Change in View: Principles of Reasoning , 1988 .

[29]  A Schlottmann,et al.  Belief revision in children: serial judgment in social cognition and decision-making domains. , 1995, Journal of experimental psychology. Learning, memory, and cognition.

[30]  P. N. Johnson-Laird,et al.  Changing your mind , 2009, Memory & cognition.

[31]  R. Elio How to Disbelieve p>q: Resolving contradictions , 1998 .

[32]  N. Cliff Dominance statistics: Ordinal analyses to answer ordinal questions. , 1993 .

[33]  P G rdenfors,et al.  Knowledge in flux: modeling the dynamics of epistemic states , 1988 .

[34]  P. Thagard,et al.  Explanatory coherence , 1993 .

[35]  A. Tversky,et al.  Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment , 1983 .

[36]  R. Shillcock,et al.  Proceedings of the Twenty-Sixth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society , 1998 .

[37]  Niki Pfeifer,et al.  Uncertain deductive reasoning , 2010 .

[38]  R. Jeffrey Formal Logic: Its Scope and Limits , 1981 .

[39]  Panagiotis G. Ipeirotis,et al.  Running Experiments on Amazon Mechanical Turk , 2010, Judgment and Decision Making.

[40]  P. Johnson-Laird,et al.  Explanations make inconsistencies harder to detect , 2010 .

[41]  Jürgen Dix,et al.  Nonmonotonic Reasoning: An Overview , 1997, CSLI Lecture Notes.

[42]  Paul D. Allopenna,et al.  The locus of knowledge effects in concept learning. , 1994, Journal of experimental psychology. Learning, memory, and cognition.

[43]  W. H. F. Barnes The Nature of Explanation , 1944, Nature.

[44]  C. Legare Exploring explanation: explaining inconsistent evidence informs exploratory, hypothesis-testing behavior in young children. , 2012, Child development.

[45]  P. Johnson-Laird,et al.  Reasoning from inconsistency to consistency. , 2004, Psychological review.