Chinese Rooms and Program Portability

I argue in this article that there is a mistake in Searle's Chinese room argument that has not received sufficient attention. The mistake stems from Searle's use of the Church–Turing thesis. Searle assumes that the Church–Turing thesis licences the assumption that the Chinese room can run any program. I argue that it does not, and that this assumption is false. A number of possible objections are considered and rejected. My conclusion is that it is consistent with Searle's argument to hold onto the claim that understanding consists in the running of a program. 1. Searle's Argument1.1. The Church–Turing thesis2. Criticism of Searle's Argument3. Objections and Replies3.1. The virtual brain machine objection3.2. The brain-based objection3.3. The syntax/physics objection3.4. The abstraction objection3.5. The ‘same conclusion’ objection3.6. The ‘unnecessary baggage’ objection3.7. The Chinese gym objection3.8. The syntax/semantics objection3.9. Turing's definition of algorithm3.9.1. Consequences3.9.2. Criticism of the defence4. Conclusion Searle's Argument The Church–Turing thesis Criticism of Searle's Argument Objections and Replies The virtual brain machine objection The brain-based objection The syntax/physics objection The abstraction objection The ‘same conclusion’ objection The ‘unnecessary baggage’ objection The Chinese gym objection The syntax/semantics objection Turing's definition of algorithm Consequences Criticism of the defence Conclusion

[1]  B. Jack Copeland,et al.  Turing’s O-machines, Searle, Penrose and the brain , 1998 .

[2]  B. J. Copeland,et al.  The curious case of the Chinese gym , 1993, Synthese.

[3]  D. Dennett The milk of human intentionality , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[4]  J. W. Backus,et al.  Can programming be liberated from the von Neumann style , 1977 .

[5]  W. Lycan The functionalist reply (Ohio State) , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[6]  J. Fodor The Language of Thought , 1980 .

[7]  Richard P. Hopkins,et al.  Data-Driven and Demand-Driven Computer Architecture , 1982, CSUR.

[8]  N. Block What intuitions about homunculi don't show , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[9]  H. Clark Barrett,et al.  Enzymatic computation and cognitive modularity , 2005 .

[10]  Ananth Grama,et al.  A Survey of Parallel Search Algorithms for Discrete , 1993 .

[11]  Georges Rey What's really going on in Searle's “Chinese room” , 1986 .

[12]  J. Searle The Rediscovery of the Mind , 1992 .

[13]  Lawrence D. Roberts Searle's extension of the Chinese room to connectionist machines , 1990, J. Exp. Theor. Artif. Intell..

[14]  BackusJohn Can programming be liberated from the von Neumann style , 1978 .

[15]  A. Turing On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem. , 1937 .

[16]  B. Libet Mental phenomena and behavior , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[17]  Z. Pylyshyn The ‘causal power’ of machines , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[18]  J. Fodor Searle on what only brains can do , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[19]  John R. Searle,et al.  Minds, brains, and programs , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[20]  John W. Backus,et al.  Can programming be liberated from the von Neumann style?: a functional style and its algebra of programs , 1978, CACM.

[21]  Samuel D. Guttenplan,et al.  A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind , 2002 .

[22]  J. Searle,et al.  Is the brain's mind a computer program? , 1990, Scientific American.