Avoiding transgenerational risks of mitochondrial DNA disorders: a morally acceptable reason for sex selection?

In this article, we discuss sex selection not intended to help a couple avoid having a child with a severe genetic disorder, but to avoid possible health risks further along the line of generations. Sex selection may be put to this use in the context of preventing mitochondrial DNA disorders by means of preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) and possibly in the future also through nuclear transfer (NT; also known as mitochondrial gene replacement). A relevant analogy can be found in the context of PGD for X-linked diseases, where sex selection against healthy female carrier embryos would have the same 2-fold purpose of (i) avoiding difficult reproductive decisions for the future child and (ii) avoiding transmission of the mutation to a possible third generation. Because sex selection would still be done for reasons of health, this application should not give rise to the moral concerns associated with sex selection for non-medical reasons. However, the proportionality of adding the relevant procedures to PGD or NT is a relevant concern. We discuss post- and preconceptional sex selection strategies. We conclude that if PGD is already part of the procedure, either as the central technology or as a back-up test after NT, preferentially transferring male embryos could in principle be a morally acceptable way of reducing possible burdens and risks. To start an IVF/PGD-cycle especially for this purpose would be disproportional. The alternative approach of preconceptional sex selection may be morally justified as a means to increase the chances of obtaining male embryos.

[1]  Georg Spielthenner,et al.  A Logical Analysis of Slippery Slope Arguments , 2010, Health Care Analysis.

[2]  V. Macaulay,et al.  Information for genetic management of mtDNA disease: sampling pathogenic mtDNA mutants in the human germline and in placenta , 2009, Journal of Medical Genetics.

[3]  Y. Li,et al.  Mitochondrial Gene Replacement in Primate Offspring and Embryonic Stem Cells , 2009, Nature.

[4]  Jah-yao Liu,et al.  Boy born after gender preselection following successive gestational androgen excess of maternal luteoma and female disorders of sex development. , 2009, Fertility and sterility.

[5]  A. Bredenoord,et al.  Preimplantation genetic diagnosis for mitochondrial DNA disorders: ethical guidance for clinical practice , 2009, European Journal of Human Genetics.

[6]  D. Wells,et al.  Preventing transmission of maternally inherited mitochondrial DNA diseases , 2009, BMJ : British Medical Journal.

[7]  Andrew Cole,et al.  More treatment in surgeries and at home will help cut NHS carbon footprint , 2009, BMJ : British Medical Journal.

[8]  H. Baharvand,et al.  Separation of X- and Y-bearing human spermatozoa by sperm isolation medium gradients evaluated by FISH. , 2009, Reproductive biomedicine online.

[9]  D. Karabinus Flow cytometric sorting of human sperm: MicroSort clinical trial update. , 2009, Theriogenology.

[10]  A. Bredenoord,et al.  Ooplasmic and nuclear transfer to prevent mitochondrial DNA disorders: conceptual and normative issues. , 2008, Human reproduction update.

[11]  A. Bredenoord,et al.  PGD to reduce reproductive risk: the case of mitochondrial DNA disorders. , 2008, Human reproduction.

[12]  J. Hayashi,et al.  Reverse genetic studies of mitochondrial DNA-based diseases using a mouse model , 2008, Proceedings of the Japan Academy. Series B, Physical and biological sciences.

[13]  David C Samuels,et al.  A reduction of mitochondrial DNA molecules during embryogenesis explains the rapid segregation of genotypes , 2008, Nature Genetics.

[14]  Dt Brown,et al.  Transmission of mitochondrial DNA disorders: possibilities for the future , 2006, The Lancet.

[15]  Laura C. Greaves,et al.  Mitochondrial DNA mutations in human disease , 2006, IUBMB life.

[16]  H. Yonekawa,et al.  Gene therapy for progeny of mito-mice carrying pathogenic mtDNA by nuclear transplantation. , 2005, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America.

[17]  T. Bourgeron,et al.  Clinical presentation of mitochondrial disorders in childhood , 1996, Journal of Inherited Metabolic Disease.

[18]  G. de Wert Preimplantation genetic diagnosis: the ethics of intermediate cases. , 2005, Human reproduction.

[19]  J. Schulman,et al.  Scientific aspects of preconception gender selection. , 2005, Reproductive biomedicine online.

[20]  G. Lucarelli,et al.  Stem cell transplantation for thalassaemia. , 2005, Reproductive biomedicine online.

[21]  G. Pennings Personal desires of patients and social obligations of geneticists: applying preimplantation genetic diagnosis for non‐medical sex selection , 2002, Prenatal diagnosis.

[22]  J. Poulton,et al.  Segregation of mitochondrial DNA (mtDNA) in human oocytes and in animal models of mtDNA disease: clinical implications. , 2002, Reproduction.

[23]  H. Dahl,et al.  Mitochondrial disorders: genetics, counseling, prenatal diagnosis and reproductive options. , 2001, American journal of medical genetics.

[24]  Preconception gender selection for nonmedical reasons. , 2001, Fertility and sterility.

[25]  R. Roberts Prevention of human mitochondrial (mtDNA) disease by nucleus transplantation into an enucleated donor oocyte. , 1999, American journal of medical genetics.

[26]  G. Pennings Measuring the welfare of the child: in search of the appropriate evaluation principle. , 1999, Human reproduction.

[27]  C. Overall The Future of human reproduction , 1992 .

[28]  A. H. Handyside,et al.  Pregnancies from biopsied human preimplantation embryos sexed by Y-specific DNA amplification , 1990, Nature.

[29]  J. Puma Gendercide: The Implications of Sex Selection , 1987 .