Doing without representing?

Connectionism and classicism, it generally appears, have at least this much in common: both place some notion of internal representation at the heart of a scientific study of mind. In recent years, however, a much more radical view has gained increasing popularity. This view calls into question the commitment to internal representation itself. More strikingly still, this new wave of anti-representationalism is rooted not in ‘armchair’ theorizing but in practical attempts to model and understand intelligent, adaptive behavior. In this paper we first present, and then critically assess, a variety of recent anti-representationalist treatments. We suggest that so far, at least, the sceptical rhetoric outpaces both evidence and argument. Some probable causes of this premature scepticism are isolated. Nonetheless, the anti-representationalist challenge is shown to be both important and progressive insofar as it forces us to see beyond the bare representational/non-representational dichotomy and to recognize instead a rich continuum of degrees and types of representationality.

[1]  T. Gelder,et al.  What Might Cognition Be, If Not Computation? , 1995 .

[2]  P. Libby The Scientific American , 1881, Nature.

[3]  Tim van Gelder,et al.  Compositionality: A Connectionist Variation on a Classical Theme , 1990, Cogn. Sci..

[4]  R. Abraham,et al.  Dynamics--the geometry of behavior , 1983 .

[5]  M. Corbetta,et al.  Selective and divided attention during visual discriminations of shape, color, and speed: functional anatomy by positron emission tomography , 1991, The Journal of neuroscience : the official journal of the Society for Neuroscience.

[6]  Andy Clark The Presence of a Symbol , 1992 .

[7]  J. Fodor,et al.  Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis , 1988, Cognition.

[8]  Allen Newell,et al.  Human Problem Solving. , 1973 .

[9]  D. Rumelhart,et al.  Philosophy and Connectionist Theory , 1991 .

[10]  Randall D. Beer,et al.  Computational and dynamical languages for autonomous agents , 1996 .

[11]  James L. McClelland,et al.  A distributed, developmental model of word recognition and naming. , 1989, Psychological review.

[12]  Geoffrey E. Hinton,et al.  Distributed Representations , 1986, The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence.

[13]  Dennis L. Sepper Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I , 1991 .

[14]  James L. McClelland,et al.  On learning the past-tenses of English verbs: implicit rules or parallel distributed processing , 1986 .

[15]  Robert F. Port,et al.  Representation and Recognition of Temporal Patterns , 1990 .

[16]  Robert F. Port,et al.  Beyond Symbolic: Prolegomena to a Kama-Sutra of Compositionality1 , 1993 .

[17]  D C Plaut,et al.  Simulating brain damage. , 1993, Scientific American.

[18]  Axel Cleeremans,et al.  Mechanisms of Implicit Learning: Connectionist Models of Sequence Processing , 1993 .

[19]  Randall D. Beer,et al.  Evolving Dynamical Neural Networks for Adaptive Behavior , 1992, Adapt. Behav..

[20]  Bruno A. Olshausen,et al.  Dynamic routing strategies in sensory, motor, and cognitive processing , 1994 .

[21]  J. Elman Distributed representations, simple recurrent networks, and grammatical structure , 1991, Machine Learning.

[22]  Stevan Harnad,et al.  Cognition is categorization , 2005 .

[23]  W. Freeman Second Commentary: On the proper treatment of connectionism by Paul Smolensky (1988) - Neuromachismo Rekindled , 1989 .

[24]  Terrence J. Sejnowski,et al.  The Computational Brain , 1996, Artif. Intell..

[25]  R. A. Brooks,et al.  Intelligence without Representation , 1991, Artif. Intell..

[26]  Marco Giunti,et al.  Computers, dynamical systems, phenomena, and the mind , 1992 .

[27]  James L. McClelland,et al.  James L. McClelland, David Rumelhart and the PDP Research Group, Parallel distributed processing: explorations in the microstructure of cognition . Vol. 1. Foundations . Vol. 2. Psychological and biological models . Cambridge MA: M.I.T. Press, 1987. , 1989, Journal of Child Language.

[28]  H. Dreyfus,et al.  Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time. , 1990 .

[29]  P. Churchland A neurocomputational perspective , 1989 .

[30]  Steven Pinker,et al.  On language and connectionism , 1988 .

[31]  Marco Giunti Computers, Dynamical Systems, Phenomena, and the Mind. PhD dissertation, Dept. of History and Philosophy of Science, Indiana University, 1992. Advisor: John Winnie. UMI Publication Number: 9301444 , 1992 .

[32]  Richard G. Kurial,et al.  Representation and recognition , 1990 .

[33]  P. Smolensky On the proper treatment of connectionism , 1988, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[34]  Martin Heidegger,et al.  A commentary on Heidegger's Being and time , 1970 .

[35]  R. Hepburn,et al.  BEING AND TIME , 2010 .

[36]  J. Fodor Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind , 1988 .

[37]  Patrik Larsson,et al.  A Distributed Neural Network Architecture for Hexapod Robot Locomotion , 1992, Neural Computation.

[38]  Jerry A. Fodor Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind: MIT Press , 1987 .

[39]  James L. McClelland,et al.  Parallel distributed processing: explorations in the microstructure of cognition, vol. 1: foundations , 1986 .

[40]  DH Hubel,et al.  Psychophysical evidence for separate channels for the perception of form, color, movement, and depth , 1987, The Journal of neuroscience : the official journal of the Society for Neuroscience.

[41]  S. Pinker,et al.  On language and connectionism: Analysis of a parallel distributed processing model of language acquisition , 1988, Cognition.

[42]  Randall D. Beer,et al.  A Dynamical Systems Perspective on Agent-Environment Interaction , 1995, Artif. Intell..

[43]  Zenon W. Pylyshyn,et al.  Connectionism and cognitive architecture , 1993 .