What Does Newcomb's Paradox Teach Us?

In Newcomb's paradox you choose to receive either the contents of a particular closed box, or the contents of both that closed box and another one. Before you choose, a prediction algorithm deduces your choice, and fills the two boxes based on that deduction. Newcomb's paradox is that game theory appears to provide two conflicting recommendations for what choice you should make in this scenario. We analyze Newcomb's paradox using a recent extension of game theory in which the players set conditional probability distributions in a Bayes net. We show that the two game theory recommendations in Newcomb's scenario have different presumptions for what Bayes net relates your choice and the algorithm's prediction. We resolve the paradox by proving that these two Bayes nets are incompatible. We also show that the accuracy of the algorithm's prediction, the focus of much previous work, is irrelevant. In addition we show that Newcomb's scenario only provides a contradiction between game theory's expected utility and dominance principles if one is sloppy in specifying the underlying Bayes net. We also show that Newcomb's paradox is time-reversal invariant; both the paradox and its resolution are unchanged if the algorithm makes its 'prediction' after you make your choice rather than before.

[1]  P.-M. Binder,et al.  Philosophy of science: Theories of almost everything , 2008, Nature.

[2]  M. Dufwenberg Game theory. , 2011, Wiley interdisciplinary reviews. Cognitive science.

[3]  William Harper,et al.  Counterfactuals and Two Kinds of Expected Utility , 1978 .

[4]  Roger B. Myerson,et al.  Game theory - Analysis of Conflict , 1991 .

[5]  Ariel Rubinstein,et al.  A Course in Game Theory , 1995 .

[6]  Richmond Campbell,et al.  Paradoxes of Rationality and Cooperation: Prisoner's Dilemma and Newcomb's Problem , 1986 .

[7]  Jorge Nuno Silva,et al.  Mathematical Games , 1959, Nature.

[8]  C. Starmer Developments in Non-expected Utility Theory: The Hunt for a Descriptive Theory of Choice under Risk , 2000 .

[9]  N. Jacobi Newcomb's paradox: A realist resolution , 1993 .

[10]  David H. Wolpert,et al.  Inference Concerning Physical Systems , 2010, CiE.

[11]  M. Bar-Hillel,et al.  Newcomb's Paradox Revisited , 1972, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

[12]  A. Inkeles,et al.  International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. , 1968 .

[13]  Daphne Koller,et al.  Multi-Agent Influence Diagrams for Representing and Solving Games , 2001, IJCAI.

[14]  Marcel Boumans,et al.  J. Pearl, Causality, Models, Reasoning, and Inference , 2005 .

[15]  David H. Wolpert,et al.  Physical limits of inference , 2007, ArXiv.

[16]  J. Berger Statistical Decision Theory and Bayesian Analysis , 1988 .

[17]  Theories of almost everything , 2022 .

[18]  J. Sladkowski,et al.  Quantum solution to the Newcomb's paradox , 2002 .

[19]  Isaac Levi,et al.  A Note on Newcombmania , 1982 .

[20]  Branden Fitelson,et al.  Newcomb's Problem , 2001 .

[21]  Simon Burgess,et al.  The Newcomb Problem: An Unqualified Resolution , 2004, Synthese.

[22]  J. Pearl Causality: Models, Reasoning and Inference , 2000 .

[23]  D. Hunter,et al.  Counterfactuals and Newcomb's paradox , 1978, Synthese.

[24]  Federico Poloni Of Note , 2009 .

[25]  John Geanakoplos,et al.  The Hangman's Paradox and Newcomb's Paradox as Psychological Games , 1996 .

[26]  Robert Nozick,et al.  Newcomb’s Problem and Two Principles of Choice , 1969 .