Criminal Liability and 'Smart' Environments

Smart applications are said to be adaptive to differing circumstances. They ‘learn’ about the best way to achieve the goals for which they have been programmed. Smart environments are said to be proactive with regard to the preferences of their users and the risks they run. Ambient Intelligence, ubiquitous, pervasive or autonomic computing all concern visions of a new socio-technical infrastructure that manages to always stay one step ahead of its human users. These environments are meant to take a whole range of decisions, having real consequences for their ‘users’. The ‘intelligence’ that is said to enable ‘smart’ decision-making thrives on the connectivity between different devices and cannot always be traced to one particular device or to one particular natural or legal person. It seems that we have a new kind of collective ‘agency’ here that may be entirely nonhuman or a complex hybrid of human and nonhuman entanglements. If these nonhuman or hybrid ‘agents’ cause harm to others a series of questions come to mind: to what extent can such agency be identified as ‘causing’ harm; what is the meaning of ‘intent’, ‘intention’ and ‘mens rea’ in the case of nonhuman agency; do we need to revise our conceptions of agency, causality, intent, intention and mens rea to accommodate the fact that nonhuman or hybrid ‘agents’ do not fit our traditional conceptual framework, or, alternatively, should we reject applicability of the criminal law in cases that fall outside the scope of human intention as we presently understand it. In the case we opt for non-applicability of the criminal law the question is raised of how will we deal with harm caused for which we cannot attribute criminal liability, due to the fact that the technological infrastructure seems to have ‘caused’ the harm. This, in its turn, requires a discussion of whether the ‘acts’ of the technological architecture will have a status similar to ‘acts of Nature’ or ‘acts of God’.

[1]  Jordi Vallverdú,et al.  The Panic Room: On Synthetic Emotions , 2008 .

[2]  Isaiah Berlin,et al.  Two Concepts of Liberty , 1958 .

[3]  Hubert L. Dreyfus,et al.  What computers still can't do - a critique of artificial reason , 1992 .

[4]  Steffen Wettig,et al.  A legal analysis of human and electronic agents , 2004, Artificial Intelligence and Law.

[5]  K. Himma Artificial agency, consciousness, and the criteria for moral agency: what properties must an artificial agent have to be a moral agent? , 2009, Ethics and Information Technology.

[6]  Luciano Floridi,et al.  On the Morality of Artificial Agents , 2004, Minds and Machines.

[7]  Curtis E. A. Karnow The Encrypted Self: Fleshing Out the Rights of Electronic Personalities, 13 J. Marshall J. Computer & Info. L. 1 (1994) , 1994 .

[8]  J. Searle The Construction of Social Reality , 1997 .

[9]  Andy Clark,et al.  Natural-Born Cyborgs? , 2001, Cognitive Technology.

[10]  C. Don Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain , 2004 .

[11]  Don Tapscott,et al.  Grown Up Digital: How the Net Generation is Changing Your World , 2008 .

[12]  H. Plessner Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch : Einleitung in die philosophische Anthropologie , 1928 .

[13]  Ilya Prigogine,et al.  Order out of chaos , 1984 .

[14]  David J. Calverley,et al.  Imagining a non-biological machine as a legal person , 2008, AI & SOCIETY.

[15]  Matthias Mahlmann Ethics, Law and the Challenge of Cognitive Science , 2007, German Law Journal.

[16]  L. Floridi,et al.  Artificial evil and the foundation of computer ethics , 2001, Ethics and Information Technology.

[17]  John R. Searle,et al.  Minds, brains, and programs , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[18]  Kurt Gray,et al.  Moral typecasting: divergent perceptions of moral agents and moral patients. , 2009, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[19]  P. Ricoeur,et al.  Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences: Essays on Language, Action and Interpretation , 2016 .

[20]  Mireille Hildebrandt,et al.  Law at a Crossroads: Losing the Thread or Regaining Control? The Collapse of Distance in Real Time Computing , 2009 .

[21]  Mireille Hildebrandt,et al.  Ambient Intelligence, Criminal Liability and Democracy , 2008 .

[22]  木島 泰三 書評 アントニオ・ダマシオ著『スピノザを探して』(未邦訳)--Antonio Damasio, Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain, Harcourt, 2003 , 2005 .

[23]  S. Morse Brain Overclaim Syndrome and Criminal Responsibility: A Diagnostic Note , 2006 .

[24]  Katherine Hayles,et al.  How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature and Informatics , 2001 .

[25]  Tom Regan,et al.  The Animal Rights Debate , 2001 .

[26]  S. Gallagher,et al.  The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science , 2007 .

[27]  Samir Chopra,et al.  Artificial Agents - Personhood in Law and Philosophy , 2004, ECAI.

[28]  Toby E. Huff,et al.  The rise of early modern science , 1993 .

[29]  S. Preston,et al.  Empathy: Its ultimate and proximate bases. , 2001, The Behavioral and brain sciences.

[30]  Joel Garreau Radical Evolution: The Promise and Peril of Enhancing Our Minds, Our Bodies -- and What It Means to Be Human , 2005 .

[31]  Gunther Teubner,et al.  Rights of Non-Humans? Electronic Agents and Animals as New Actors in Politics and Law , 2006 .

[32]  Lawrence B. Solum Legal Personhood for Artificial Intelligences , 2008, Machine Ethics and Robot Ethics.

[33]  Jeffrey O. Kephart,et al.  The Vision of Autonomic Computing , 2003, Computer.