It has been said that modal logic consists of three main disciplines: duality theory, completeness theory and correspondence theory; and that they are the pillars on which this edifice called modal logic rests. This seems to be true if one looks at the history of modal logic, for all three disciplines have been explicitly defined around the same time, namely in the mid-seventies. While it is certainly true that modal logic can be divided in this way, such a division creates the danger that the subareas are developed merely in their own right, disregarding the obvious connections between them. Moreover, such historically grown divisions always run a risk of enshrining certain errors that have accidentally been made and subsequently hindered the development. One such error is the idea that Kripke-frames are the natural or fundamental semantics for modal logic. Although I agree that Kripke-models are the most intuitive models and that they are in many cases indeed the intended models, I cannot go along with the claim that they are in any stronger sense fundamental. Philosophically as well as mathematically, to start with Kripke-frames is to start at the wrong end; philosophically, because nothing warrants the belief that possible worlds exist — in fact, for my ears this is a contradictio in adiectu — and indeed it is much more plausible to say that possible worlds are philosophical fiction. And mathematically, because Kripke-frames are deficient in some respects and these deficiencies do not apply to modal algebras and also because the former can be obtained canonically from the latter. It is surprising how long it was possible to ignore Stone’s representation theory for boolean algebras and also Tarski’s work together with Jonsson in which Kripke-semantics appeared long before Kripke himself came to discover it.
[1]
Max J. Cresswell,et al.
A companion to modal logic
,
1984
.
[2]
K. Fine.
Logics containing K4. Part II
,
1985,
Journal of Symbolic Logic.
[3]
Marcus Kracht,et al.
Internal Definability And Completeness In Modal Logic
,
1990
.
[4]
Robert Goldblatt.
The McKinsey Axiom Is Not Canonical
,
1991,
J. Symb. Log..
[5]
Kit Fine,et al.
Logics containing K4. Part I
,
1974,
Journal of Symbolic Logic.
[6]
K. Fine.
Some Connections Between Elementary and Modal Logic
,
1975
.
[7]
A. Tarski,et al.
Boolean Algebras with Operators. Part I
,
1951
.
[8]
S. Kanger.
Proceedings of the third Scandinavian Logic Symposium
,
1975
.
[9]
J. Benthem.
Some kinds of modal completeness
,
1980
.
[10]
Michael Zakharyaschev,et al.
Canonical formulas for K4. Part I: Basic results
,
1992,
Journal of Symbolic Logic.
[11]
Robert Goldblatt,et al.
Varieties of Complex Algebras
,
1989,
Ann. Pure Appl. Log..
[12]
A. Tarski,et al.
Boolean Algebras with Operators
,
1952
.
[13]
Lilia Chagrova,et al.
An undecidable problem in correspondence theory
,
1991,
Journal of Symbolic Logic.
[14]
M. V. Zakhar'yashchev.
Syntax and semantics of modal logics containing S4
,
1988
.
[15]
Giovanni Sambin,et al.
Topology and duality in modal logic
,
1988,
Ann. Pure Appl. Log..
[16]
Wolfgang Rautenberg,et al.
Klassische und nichtklassische Aussagenlogik
,
1979
.
[17]
Giovanni Sambin,et al.
A new proof of Sahlqvist's theorem on modal definability and completeness
,
1989,
Journal of Symbolic Logic.
[18]
Johan van Benthem,et al.
Notes on Modal Definability
,
1988,
Notre Dame J. Formal Log..
[19]
R. Goldblatt.
Metamathematics of modal logic
,
1974,
Bulletin of the Australian Mathematical Society.