Some effort for some: Further evidence that scalar implicatures are effortful

Under the assumption of the principle of cooperation (Grice, 1989), a statement such as “some eels are fish” is thought to be false since it contains less information than is considered sufficient. However, the statement is logically sound since the meaning of “some” is compatible with “all”. Currently, the primary interpretation of such underinformative statements remains subject to debate. According to Levinson (2000), the pragmatic “some but not all” interpretation is the default interpretation, while others (e.g., Sperber & Wilson, 1995) argue that this pragmatic interpretation only comes to the fore when relevant within the context and is thus considered secondary to the logical “some and perhaps all” interpretation. In this study, three factors that may influence the answer pattern are studied: task load, working memory capacity, and repetition of the statements. In Experiment 1, we used a secondary task paradigm to manipulate the cognitive load under which a number of underinformative statements had to be judged. We observed that for participants with a rather limited working memory span it is harder to reach a pragmatic interpretation under cognitive load. In Experiment 2, we manipulated the repetition of the statements. We observed that with a higher number of filler statements, participants produced fewer consistent answer patterns. This study provides further evidence against the automaticity of the pragmatic interpretation: It shows that the pragmatic interpretation requires more cognitive effort than the logical interpretation and that increasing the number of filler statements inhibits the development of a response strategy.

[1]  Laurence R. Horn,et al.  On the semantic properties of logical operators in english' reproduced by the indiana university lin , 1972 .

[2]  L. Rips Quantification and semantic memory , 1975, Cognitive Psychology.

[3]  Walter Schneider,et al.  Controlled and automatic human information processing: II. Perceptual learning, automatic attending and a general theory. , 1977 .

[4]  P. Carpenter,et al.  Individual differences in working memory and reading , 1980 .

[5]  Carol L. Smith Quantifiers and Question Answering in Young Children. , 1980 .

[6]  D. Sperber,et al.  Relevance: Communication and Cognition , 1997 .

[7]  C. E. Bethell-Fox,et al.  Mental rotation: effects of stimulus complexity and familiarity , 1988 .

[8]  Laurence R. Horn A Natural History of Negation , 1989 .

[9]  D. Over,et al.  Studies in the Way of Words. , 1989 .

[10]  Randall W. Engle,et al.  Simple and complex word spans as measures of working memory capacity. , 1990 .

[11]  A. Avramides Studies in the Way of Words , 1992 .

[12]  A. Baddeley Exploring the Central Executive , 1996 .

[13]  Robyn Carston,et al.  Informativeness, relevance and scalar implicature , 1998 .

[14]  Robyn Carston,et al.  Relevance theory : applications and implications , 1998 .

[15]  Deirdre Wilson,et al.  Relevance theory: A tutorial , 2002 .

[16]  木村 和夫 Pragmatics , 1997, Language Teaching.

[17]  S. Levinson Presumptive Meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature , 2001 .

[18]  M. Botvinick,et al.  Conflict monitoring and cognitive control. , 2001, Psychological review.

[19]  David A. Rettinger,et al.  How are visuospatial working memory, executive functioning, and spatial abilities related? A latent-variable analysis. , 2001, Journal of experimental psychology. General.

[20]  I. Noveck When children are more logical than adults: experimental investigations of scalar implicature , 2001, Cognition.

[21]  Walter Schaeken,et al.  A Dutch, computerized, and group administrable adaptation of the operation span test , 2002 .

[22]  R. Engle Working Memory Capacity as Executive Attention , 2002 .

[23]  I. Noveck,et al.  Characterizing the time course of an implicature: An evoked potentials study , 2003, Brain and Language.

[24]  A. Papafragou,et al.  Scalar implicatures: experiments at the semantics–pragmatics interface , 2003, Cognition.

[25]  A. Feeney,et al.  The story of some: everyday pragmatic inference by children and adults. , 2004, Canadian journal of experimental psychology = Revue canadienne de psychologie experimentale.

[26]  Robin K. Morris,et al.  Implicature, Relevance and Default Pragmatic Inference , 2004 .

[27]  Lewis Bott,et al.  Some utterances are underinformative: The onset and time course of scalar inferences , 2004 .

[28]  S. Crain,et al.  Why children and adults sometimes (but not always) compute implicatures , 2005 .

[29]  John N. Williams,et al.  Are generalised scalar implicatures generated by default? An on-line investigation into the role of context in generating pragmatic inferences , 2006, Cognition.

[30]  L. Gleitman,et al.  Asymmetries in the Acquisition of Numbers and Quantifiers , 2006 .

[31]  Wim De Neys,et al.  Dual Processing in Reasoning , 2006, Psychological science.

[32]  Wim De Neys,et al.  Automatic-heuristic and executive-analytic processing during reasoning: Chronometric and dual-task considerations. , 2006 .

[33]  W. Schaeken,et al.  When people are more logical under cognitive load: dual task impact on scalar implicature. , 2007, Experimental psychology.

[34]  Sonja M. Geiger,et al.  Two meanings of “if”? Individual differences in the interpretation of conditionals , 2007, Quarterly journal of experimental psychology.

[35]  I. Noveck,et al.  A Developmental Investigation of Processing Costs in Implicature Production , 2007 .

[36]  Robyn Carston,et al.  Relevance Theory and the saying/implicating distinction , 2008 .

[37]  Lewis Bott,et al.  Making disjunctions exclusive , 2008, Quarterly journal of experimental psychology.

[38]  I. Noveck,et al.  Experimental Pragmatics: a Gricean turn in the study of language , 2008, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.