Problems of Reification: Representations and Mathematical Objects

Had Bishop Berkeley, as many fine minds before and after him, not criticized the ill-defined concept of infinitesimal, mathematical analysis — one of the most elegant theories in mathematics — could have not been born. On the other hand, had Berkeley launched his attack through Internet, the whole foundational effort might have taken a few decades rather than one and one-half centuries. This is what we were reminded of when starting our discussion. Like Berkeley, we were dealing with a theory that works but is still in a need of better foundations. Unlike Berkeley and those after him, we had only a few months to finish, and we had e-mail at our disposal. Needless to say, the theory we were concerned with, called reification, was nothing as grandiose and central as mathematical analysis. It was merely one of several recently-constructed frameworks for investigating mathematical learning and problem solving. The example of Bishop Berkeley taught us there is nothing more fruitful than a good disagreement. Thus, we decided to play roles, namely to agree to disagree. Since we are, in fact, quite close to each other in our thinking, we sometimes had to polarize our positions for the sake of a better argument. The subject proved richer and more intricate than we could dream. Inevitably, our discussion led us to places we did not plan to visit. When scrutinizing the theoretical constructs, we often felt forced to go meta-theoretical and tackle such basic quandaries as what counts as acceptable theory — or why we need theory at all. Above all, we enjoyed ourselves. We also believe it was more than fun, and we hope we made some progress. Whether we did, and whether our fun may be shared with others, is for you to judge. The following excerpt appears in Research in Collegiate Mathematics Education. In it I speak about the " fiction " of multiple-representations of function—I do not speak about reification 2 Thompson & Sfard as such. However, I think what I said about functions is applicable in the more general case of reification, too: That we experience the subjective sense of " mathematical object " because we build abstractions of representational activity in specific contexts and form connections among those activities by way of a sort of " semantic identity. " We represent to ourselves aspects of (what we take to be) the same situation in multiple ways, …

[1]  Patrick Thompson,et al.  Problems of reification: Representations and mathematical objects. In D. Kirshner , 1994 .

[2]  T. Kuhn,et al.  Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge: Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research? , 1970 .

[3]  W. Dörfler,et al.  Mathematical Objects, Representations, and Imagery , 1995 .

[4]  Patrick W Thompson,et al.  Artificial Intelligence, Advanced Technology, and Learning and Teaching Algebra , 2018, Research Issues in the Learning and Teaching of Algebra.

[5]  Patrick W Thompson Experience, Problem Solving, and Learning Mathematics: Considerations in Developing Mathematics Curricula , 1985 .

[6]  L. Viennot Fundamental Patterns in Common Reasoning: examples in Physics , 1994 .

[7]  L. Brouwer,et al.  HISTORICAL BACKGROUND, PRINCIPLES AND METHODS OF INTUITIONISM , 1975 .

[8]  J. Sayers Against Method , 2016 .

[9]  Patrick W Thompson Getting Ahead: With Theories * I Have a Theory About This , 1991 .

[10]  T. Kuhn The structure of scientific revolutions, 3rd ed. , 1996 .

[11]  G. Eisenstein,et al.  The Postmodern Explained , 1995 .

[12]  Patrick W Thompson,et al.  The development of the concept of speed and its relationship to concepts of rate , 1994 .

[13]  G. Verleden,et al.  Foreword , 1992, Steroids.

[14]  T. A. A. Broadbent,et al.  Evolution of Mathematical Concepts: An Elementary Study , 1970 .

[15]  L. Brouwer CONSCIOUSNESS, PHILOSOPHY, AND MATHEMATICS , 1975 .

[16]  H. Putnam The Many Faces of Realism , 2020, Pragmatism.

[17]  Paul Cobb,et al.  Construction of Arithmetical Meanings and Strategies , 1987 .

[18]  Ed Dubinsky,et al.  Development of the process conception of function , 1992 .

[19]  David Tall,et al.  Ambiguity and flexibility: A proceptual view of simple arithmetic , 1983 .

[20]  A. Sfard Reification as the birth of metaphor , 1994 .

[21]  A. Sfard,et al.  The gains and the pitfalls of reification — The case of algebra , 1994 .

[22]  Imre Lakatos,et al.  On the Uses of Rigorous Proof. (Book Reviews: Proofs and Refutations. The Logic of Mathematical Discovery) , 1977 .

[23]  T. Broadbent,et al.  Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge , 1972 .

[24]  A. Newell A NOTE ON PROCESS-STRUCTURE DISTINCTIONS IN DEVELOPMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY , 1972 .

[25]  Patrick W Thompson To experience is to conceptualize: Discussions of epistemology and experience. , 1991 .

[26]  J. Piaget,et al.  The equilibration of cognitive structures : the central problem of intellectual development , 1985 .

[27]  A. Sfard On the dual nature of mathematical conceptions: Reflections on processes and objects as different sides of the same coin , 1991 .

[28]  Edward A. Silver,et al.  Teaching and Learning Mathematical Problem Solving : Multiple Research Perspectives , 1985 .

[29]  N. Presmeg The body in the mind: The bodily basis of meaning, imagination and reason , 1992 .

[30]  I. Lakatos Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes , 1976 .

[31]  R. Swinburne OBJECTIVE KNOWLEDGE: AN EVOLUTIONARY APPROACH , 1973 .

[32]  D. Wheeler,et al.  The arithmetic connection , 1989 .

[33]  P. W. Thompson,et al.  Students, functions, and the undergraduate mathematics curriculum. In E. Dubinsky, A. H. Schoenfeld, & J. J. Kaput (Eds.) , 1994 .

[34]  T. Kuhn,et al.  The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. , 1964 .

[35]  Karin D. Knorr,et al.  The Scientist as an Analogical Reasoner: A Critique of the Metaphor Theory of Innovation , 1980 .

[36]  K. Popper Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach , 1972 .

[37]  Karin D. Knorr,et al.  The Social process of scientific investigation , 1980 .

[38]  Leslie P. Steffe,et al.  Epistemological foundations of mathematical experience , 1991 .

[39]  R. L. Wilder Mathematics as a cultural system , 1981 .

[40]  Ernst von Glasersfeld Abstraction, Re-Presentation, and Reflection, an Interpretation of Experience and Piaget's Approach. , 1991 .

[41]  Leslie P. Steffe,et al.  Children's counting types: Philosophy, theory, and application , 1983 .

[42]  Imre Lakatos,et al.  The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes , 1978 .

[43]  Jere Confrey,et al.  The Development of multiplicative reasoning in the learning of mathematics , 1995 .

[44]  Patrick W Thompson,et al.  Were lions to speak, we wouldn’t understand , 1982 .

[45]  J. Dewey The Sources Of A Science Of Education , 1929 .

[46]  Leslie P. Steffe,et al.  Children’s Counting in Arithmetical Problem Solving , 1982 .

[47]  Patrick W. Thompson Mathematical microworlds and intelligent computer-assisted instruction , 1986 .

[48]  Randolph A. Philipp,et al.  Calculational and Conceptual Orientations in Teaching Mathematics , 1994 .

[49]  P. Cobb,et al.  A Constructivist Alternative to the Representational View of Mind in Mathematics Education. , 1992 .

[50]  S. Turkle,et al.  Epistemological Pluralism and the Revaluation of the Concrete. , 1992 .

[51]  Jean-François Lyotard,et al.  The Postmodern Condition , 1979 .

[52]  W. Thurston On Proof and Progress in Mathematics , 1994, math/9404236.

[53]  David Tall,et al.  Advanced Mathematical Thinking , 1994 .

[54]  Donald M. MacKay,et al.  Information, mechanism and meaning , 1969 .

[55]  Carolyn Kieran,et al.  Research Issues in the Learning and Teaching of Algebra , 1989 .