Extending tournament solutions

An important subclass of social choice functions, so-called majoritarian (or C1) functions, only take into account the pairwise majority relation between alternatives. In the absence of majority ties—e.g., when there is an odd number of agents with linear preferences—the majority relation is antisymmetric and complete and can thus conveniently be represented by a tournament. Tournaments have a rich mathematical theory and many formal results for majoritarian functions assume that the majority relation constitutes a tournament. Moreover, most majoritarian functions have only been defined for tournaments and allow for a variety of generalizations to unrestricted preference profiles, none of which can be seen as the unequivocal extension of the original function. In this paper, we argue that restricting attention to tournaments is justified by the existence of a conservative extension, which inherits most of the commonly considered properties from its underlying tournament solution.

[1]  Felix Brandt,et al.  Characterization of dominance relations in finite coalitional games , 2010 .

[2]  Jeffrey S. Banks,et al.  Voting games, indifference, and consistent sequential choice rules , 1988 .

[3]  A. Sen,et al.  Social Choice Theory , 2005 .

[4]  Gerhard J. Woeginger,et al.  Banks winners in tournaments are difficult to recognize , 2003, Soc. Choice Welf..

[5]  Kenneth O. May,et al.  A Set of Independent Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Simple Majority Decision , 1952 .

[6]  K. Arrow,et al.  Social Choice and Multicriterion Decision-Making , 1986 .

[7]  Felix Brandt,et al.  Tournament Solutions , 2016, Handbook of Computational Social Choice.

[8]  Piotr Faliszewski,et al.  Llull and Copeland Voting Computationally Resist Bribery and Constructive Control , 2009, J. Artif. Intell. Res..

[9]  Thierry Marchant,et al.  Evaluation and Decision Models with Multiple Criteria: Stepping Stones for the Analyst , 2006 .

[10]  Felix Brandt,et al.  Tournament Solutions Extensions of Maximality and their Applications to Decision-Making , 2009 .

[11]  A. Sen,et al.  Chapter 22 Social choice theory , 1986 .

[12]  Noga Alon,et al.  Ranking Tournaments , 2006, SIAM J. Discret. Math..

[13]  M. R. Rao,et al.  Combinatorial Optimization , 1992, NATO ASI Series.

[14]  Dominique Henriet,et al.  The Copeland choice function an axiomatic characterization , 1985 .

[15]  Felix A. Fischer,et al.  Minimal retentive sets in tournaments , 2010, AAMAS.

[16]  Felix Brandt,et al.  On the Fixed-Parameter Tractability of Composition-Consistent Tournament Solutions , 2011, IJCAI.

[17]  Felix A. Fischer,et al.  Computing the minimal covering set , 2008, Math. Soc. Sci..

[18]  Jeffrey Richelson Some Further Results on Consistency, Rationality and Collective Choice , 1978 .

[19]  Dongmo Zhang,et al.  The logic of collective choice , 1988, AAMAS.

[20]  Ayzerman,et al.  Theory of choice , 1995 .

[21]  John Duggan,et al.  Mixed refinements of Shapley's saddles and weak tournaments , 2001, Soc. Choice Welf..

[22]  Felix A. Fischer,et al.  Possible and necessary winners of partial tournaments , 2012, AAMAS.

[23]  W. A. Wallis,et al.  UNCOVERED SETS , 2011 .

[24]  Felix Brandt,et al.  Set-monotonicity implies Kelly-strategyproofness , 2010, Soc. Choice Welf..

[25]  M. Breton,et al.  The Bipartisan Set of a Tournament Game , 1993 .

[26]  Felix A. Fischer,et al.  A computational analysis of the tournament equilibrium set , 2008, Soc. Choice Welf..

[27]  F. Brandt,et al.  Computational Social Choice: Prospects and Challenges , 2011, FET.

[28]  Felix Brandt,et al.  Set-rationalizable choice and self-stability , 2009, J. Econ. Theory.

[29]  Thomas Schwartz Cyclic tournaments and cooperative majority voting: A solution , 1990 .

[30]  Jörg Rothe,et al.  The Complexity of Computing Minimal Unidirectional Covering Sets , 2010, CIAC.

[31]  Felix A. Fischer,et al.  The Price of Neutrality for the Ranked Pairs Method , 2012, AAAI.

[32]  Jean-François Laslier,et al.  Tournament Solutions And Majority Voting , 1997 .

[33]  Thierry Marchant,et al.  AND DECISION MODELS : Stepping stones for the analyst , 2003 .

[34]  Begoña Subiza Martínez,et al.  Condorcet choice correspondences for weak tournaments , 1997 .

[35]  Bhaskar Dutta,et al.  Comparison functions and choice correspondences , 1999 .

[36]  John Duggan,et al.  Dutta's Minimal Covering Set and Shapley's Saddles , 1996 .

[37]  Felix Brandt,et al.  Group-Strategyproof Irresolute Social Choice Functions , 2010, IJCAI.

[38]  Bernard Monjardet Statement of precedence and a comment on IIA terminology , 2008, Games Econ. Behav..

[39]  H. Moulin Choosing from a tournament , 1986 .

[40]  Vincent Conitzer,et al.  General Tiebreaking Schemes for Computational Social Choice , 2015, AAMAS.

[41]  Toby Walsh,et al.  Winner determination in voting trees with incomplete preferences and weighted votes , 2011, Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems.

[42]  Vincent Conitzer,et al.  Computing Possible and Necessary Equilibrium Actions (and Bipartisan Set Winners) , 2016, ISAIM.

[43]  H. Chernoff Rational Selection of Decision Functions , 1954 .

[44]  T. Schwartz Rationality and the Myth of the Maximum , 1972 .

[45]  Jennifer Ryan,et al.  Tournament games and positive tournaments , 1995, J. Graph Theory.

[46]  Jörg Rothe,et al.  The Complexity of Computing Minimal Unidirectional Covering Sets , 2009, Theory of Computing Systems.

[47]  Felix A. Fischer,et al.  The Computational Complexity of Choice Sets , 2007, TARK '07.