Voting with Limited Information and Many Alternatives

The traditional axiomatic approach to voting is motivated by the problem of reconciling differences in subjective preferences. In contrast, a dominant line of work in the theory of voting over the past 15 years has considered a different kind of scenario, also fundamental to voting, in which there is a genuinely "best" outcome that voters would agree on if they only had enough information. This type of scenario has its roots in the classical Condorcet Jury Theorem; it includes cases such as jurors in a criminal trial who all want to reach the correct verdict but disagree in their inferences from the available evidence, or a corporate board of directors who all want to improve the company's revenue, but who have different information that favors different options. This style of voting leads to a natural set of questions: each voter has a private signal that provides probabilistic information about which option is best, and a central question is whether a simple plurality voting system, which tabulates votes for different options, can cause the group decision to arrive at the correct option. We show that plurality voting is powerful enough to achieve this: there is a way for voters to map their signals into votes for options in such a way that --- with sufficiently many voters --- the correct option receives the greatest number of votes with high probability. We show further, however, that any process for achieving this is inherently expensive in the number of voters it requires: succeeding in identifying the correct option with probability at least 1 − ν requires Ω(n3e−2 log ν−1) voters, where n is the number of options and e is a distributional measure of the minimum difference between the options.

[1]  R. Myerson Extended Poisson Games and the Condorcet Jury Theorem , 1998 .

[2]  Ariel D. Procaccia,et al.  Voting almost maximizes social welfare despite limited communication , 2010, Artif. Intell..

[3]  Wolfgang Pesendorfer,et al.  Abstention in Elections with Asymmetric Information and Diverse Preferences , 1999, American Political Science Review.

[4]  Patrick Hummel Information aggregation in multicandidate elections under plurality rule and runoff voting , 2011, Math. Soc. Sci..

[5]  A. Raftery,et al.  Strictly Proper Scoring Rules, Prediction, and Estimation , 2007 .

[6]  Charles A. Holt,et al.  Information Cascades in the Laboratory , 1998 .

[7]  T. Feddersen,et al.  Convicting the Innocent: The Inferiority of Unanimous Jury Verdicts under Strategic Voting , 1996, American Political Science Review.

[8]  Marco Battaglini,et al.  The Swing Voter's Curse in the Laboratory , 2006 .

[9]  H. Young Condorcet's Theory of Voting , 1988, American Political Science Review.

[10]  Noga Alon,et al.  The Probabilistic Method , 2015, Fundamentals of Ramsey Theory.

[11]  W. Feller Generalization of a probability limit theorem of Cramér , 1943 .

[12]  Patrick Hummel,et al.  Jury theorems with multiple alternatives , 2010, Soc. Choice Welf..

[13]  Navin Kartik,et al.  Preference Reversal and Information Aggregation in Elections , 2006 .

[14]  Elchanan Mossel,et al.  From Agreement to Asymptotic Learning , 2011, 1105.4765.

[15]  T. Feddersen,et al.  The Swing Voter's Curse , 1996 .

[16]  J. Banks,et al.  Information Aggregation, Rationality, and the Condorcet Jury Theorem , 1996, American Political Science Review.