The freedoms of software and its ethical uses

The “free” in “free software” refers to a cluster of four specific freedoms identified by the Free Software Definition. The first freedom, termed “Freedom Zero,” intends to protect the right of the user to deploy software in whatever fashion, towards whatever end, he or she sees fit. But software may be used to achieve ethically questionable ends. This highlights a tension in the provision of software freedoms: while the definition explicitly forbids direct restrictions on users’ freedoms, it does not address other means by which software may indirectly restrict freedoms. In particular, ethically-inflected debate has featured prominently in the discussion of restrictions on digital rights management and privacy-violating code in version 3 of the GPL (GPLv3). The discussion of this proposed language revealed the spectrum of ethical positions and valuations held by members of the free software community. In our analysis, we will provide arguments for upholding Freedom Zero; we embed the problem of possible uses of software in the broader context of the uses of scientific knowledge, and go on to argue that the provision of Freedom Zero mitigates against too great a moral burden—of anticipating possible uses of software—being placed on the programmer and that, most importantly, it facilitates deliberative discourse in the free software community.

[1]  H. Longino Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry , 1990 .

[2]  Steven Levy,et al.  Hackers: Heroes of the Computer Revolution , 1984 .

[3]  Lawrence Lessig,et al.  Free Culture: How Big Media Uses Technology and the Law to Lock Down Culture and Control Creativity , 2004 .

[4]  PublicPolicy COMMITTEE ON SCIENCE, ENGINEERING, AND PUBLIC POLICY , 1998 .

[5]  John S. Dryzek,et al.  Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science , 1992 .

[6]  孙庆红 英语语篇中的衔接手段探析——以A Message to Intellectuals文本为例 , 2010 .

[7]  Terri Gullickson,et al.  On Being a Scientist: Responsible Conduct in Research (2nd ed). , 1996 .

[8]  Samir Chopra,et al.  A Comparative Ethical Assessment of Free Software Licensing Schemes , 2006 .

[9]  Michael Slote From Morality to Virtue , 1992 .

[10]  Dominique Brossard,et al.  Framing Science , 2003 .

[11]  Edward W. Felten,et al.  A skeptical view of DRM and fair use , 2003, CACM.

[12]  S. Parry,et al.  The politics of cloning: mapping the rhetorical convergence of embryos and stem cells in parliamentary debates , 2003, New genetics and society.

[13]  G. Mcgee,et al.  The Human Cloning Debate , 2002 .

[14]  Chris DiBona,et al.  Open Sources: Voices from the Open Source Revolution , 1999 .

[15]  Nick Couldry,et al.  Digital divide or discursive design? On the emerging ethics of information space , 2003, Ethics and Information Technology.

[16]  Andrew M. St. Laurent Understanding Open Source and Free Software Licensing , 2004 .

[17]  Westone,et al.  Home Page , 2004, 2022 2nd International Conference on Intelligent Cybernetics Technology & Applications (ICICyTA).

[18]  Axel Funk,et al.  Die GNU General Public License, Version 3 , 2007 .

[19]  Chiang Teck Meng What is Copyleft?: How it Relates to the Market Economy Driven by Proprietary Software , 2009 .

[20]  Patrick Lee Plaisance,et al.  The Mass Media as Discursive Network: Building on the Implications of Libertarian and Communitarian Claims for News Media Ethics Theory , 2005 .

[21]  Paul Kavanagh,et al.  The Open Source Definition , 2004 .

[22]  O. Walusinski,et al.  Brief biography , 1960 .

[23]  D. L. Harris,et al.  Lanoy N. Hazel, 1911-1992: a brief biography. , 1994, Journal of animal science.

[24]  H. Sidgwick The Methods of Ethics: A SUPPLEMENT TO THE FIRST EDITION OF THE METHODS OF ETHICS , 1874 .

[25]  Samir Chopra,et al.  Decoding Liberation: The Promise of Free and Open Source Software , 2007 .