Contextual utility affects the perceived quality of explanations

Are explanations of different kinds (formal, mechanistic, teleological) judged differently depending on their contextual utility, defined as the extent to which they support the kinds of inferences required for a given task? We report three studies demonstrating that the perceived “goodness” of an explanation depends on the evaluator’s current task: Explanations receive a relative boost when they support task-relevant inferences, even when all three explanation types are warranted. For example, mechanistic explanations receive higher ratings when participants anticipate making further inferences on the basis of proximate causes than when they anticipate making further inferences on the basis of category membership or functions. These findings shed light on the functions of explanation and support pragmatic and pluralist approaches to explanation.

[1]  W. H. F. Barnes The Nature of Explanation , 1944, Nature.

[2]  C. Hempel,et al.  Studies in the Logic of Explanation , 1948, Philosophy of Science.

[3]  F. Heider The psychology of interpersonal relations , 1958 .

[4]  S. Gorovitz Causal judgments and causal explanations , 1965 .

[5]  P. Railton A Deductive-Nomological Model of Probabilistic Explanation , 1978, Philosophy of Science.

[6]  Bas C. van Fraassen,et al.  The Scientific Image , 1980 .

[7]  L. Barsalou,et al.  Ad hoc categories , 1983, Memory & cognition.

[8]  J. Woodward,et al.  Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World , 1988 .

[9]  Wesley C. Salmon,et al.  Van Fraassen on Explanation , 1987 .

[10]  S. Brison The Intentional Stance , 1989 .

[11]  Ann L. McGill Context effects in judgments of causation. , 1989 .

[12]  P. Kitcher Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world , 1989 .

[13]  D. Hilton Conversational processes and causal explanation. , 1990 .

[14]  P. Lipton VI*-IS THE BEST GOOD ENOUGH? , 1993 .

[15]  N. Pennington,et al.  Reasoning in explanation-based decision making , 1993, Cognition.

[16]  Lawrence W. Barsalou,et al.  Explanation Content and Construction During System Learning and Troubleshooting , 1995 .

[17]  David B. Leake Abduction, experience, and goals: a model of everyday abductive explanation , 1995, J. Exp. Theor. Artif. Intell..

[18]  D. Hilton Mental Models and Causal Explanation: Judgements of Probable Cause and Explanatory Relevance , 1996 .

[19]  W. Ahn Why are different features central for natural kinds and artifacts?: the role of causal status in determining feature centrality , 1998, Cognition.

[20]  Steven A. Sloman,et al.  Feature Centrality and Conceptual Coherence , 1998, Cogn. Sci..

[21]  Paul Hagstrom,et al.  Is the best good enough , 1998 .

[22]  W. Ahn,et al.  Causal Status as a Determinant of Feature Centrality , 2000, Cognitive Psychology.

[23]  A. Markman,et al.  Category use and category learning. , 2003, Psychological bulletin.

[24]  Jesse L. Preston,et al.  The Explanatory Power of Valuable Beliefs , 2005 .

[25]  Russell C. Burnett,et al.  Feature inference and the causal structure of categories , 2005, Cognitive Psychology.

[26]  Bob Rehder,et al.  How causal knowledge affects classification: A generative theory of categorization. , 2006, Journal of experimental psychology. Learning, memory, and cognition.

[27]  S. Carey,et al.  Functional explanation and the function of explanation , 2006, Cognition.

[28]  Sandeep Prasada,et al.  Principled and statistical connections in common sense conception , 2006, Cognition.

[29]  Keith A. Markus,et al.  Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation , 2007 .

[30]  T. Lombrozo,et al.  Simplicity and probability in causal explanation , 2007, Cognitive Psychology.

[31]  Sandeep Prasada,et al.  Representation of Principled Connections: A Window Onto the Formal Aspect of Common Sense Conception , 2009, Cogn. Sci..

[32]  T. Lombrozo Explanation and categorization: How “why?” informs “what?” , 2009, Cognition.

[33]  Seth Chin-Parker,et al.  Background shifts affect explanatory style: how a pragmatic theory of explanation accounts for background effects in the generation of explanations , 2010, Cognitive Processing.

[34]  H. Aarts,et al.  Goals, attention, and (un)consciousness. , 2010, Annual review of psychology.

[35]  Daniel Heussen,et al.  When functions and causes compete , 2010 .

[36]  Bob Rehder,et al.  Functions in biological kind classification , 2012, Cognitive Psychology.

[37]  T. Lombrozo Explanation and Abductive Inference , 2012 .

[38]  A. Elliot,et al.  Goal-Directed Behavior , 2012 .

[39]  Joshua Rottman,et al.  Journal of Experimental Psychology : General Professional Physical Scientists Display Tenacious Teleological Tendencies : Purpose-Based Reasoning as a Cognitive Default , 2012 .

[40]  Nadya Vasilyeva,et al.  Evaluating Two Mechanisms of Flexible Induction: Selective Memory Retrieval and Evidence Explanation , 2013, CogSci.

[41]  Tania Lombrozo,et al.  Explanation and inference: mechanistic and functional explanations guide property generalization , 2014, Front. Hum. Neurosci..

[42]  Karolin Baecker,et al.  Inference to the Best Explanation: , 2021, The Material Theory of Induction.

[43]  Haley A. Vlach,et al.  Talking to children about science is harder than we think: characteristics and metacognitive judgments of explanations provided to children and adults , 2016 .

[44]  Mandy Eberhart,et al.  The Scientific Image , 2016 .